empathy essay brainly

Understanding others’ feelings: what is empathy and why do we need it?

empathy essay brainly

Senior Lecturer in Social Neuroscience, Monash University

Disclosure statement

Pascal Molenberghs receives funding from the Australian Research Council (ARC Discovery Early Career Research Award: DE130100120) and Heart Foundation (Heart Foundation Future Leader Fellowship: 1000458).

Monash University provides funding as a founding partner of The Conversation AU.

View all partners

This is the introductory essay in our series on understanding others’ feelings. In it we will examine empathy, including what it is, whether our doctors need more of it, and when too much may not be a good thing.

Empathy is the ability to share and understand the emotions of others. It is a construct of multiple components, each of which is associated with its own brain network . There are three ways of looking at empathy.

First there is affective empathy. This is the ability to share the emotions of others. People who score high on affective empathy are those who, for example, show a strong visceral reaction when watching a scary movie.

They feel scared or feel others’ pain strongly within themselves when seeing others scared or in pain.

Cognitive empathy, on the other hand, is the ability to understand the emotions of others. A good example is the psychologist who understands the emotions of the client in a rational way, but does not necessarily share the emotions of the client in a visceral sense.

Finally, there’s emotional regulation. This refers to the ability to regulate one’s emotions. For example, surgeons need to control their emotions when operating on a patient.

empathy essay brainly

Another way to understand empathy is to distinguish it from other related constructs. For example, empathy involves self-awareness , as well as distinction between the self and the other. In that sense it is different from mimicry, or imitation.

Many animals might show signs of mimicry or emotional contagion to another animal in pain. But without some level of self-awareness, and distinction between the self and the other, it is not empathy in a strict sense. Empathy is also different from sympathy, which involves feeling concern for the suffering of another person and a desire to help.

That said, empathy is not a unique human experience. It has been observed in many non-human primates and even rats .

People often say psychopaths lack empathy but this is not always the case. In fact, psychopathy is enabled by good cognitive empathic abilities - you need to understand what your victim is feeling when you are torturing them. What psychopaths typically lack is sympathy. They know the other person is suffering but they just don’t care.

Research has also shown those with psychopathic traits are often very good at regulating their emotions .

empathy essay brainly

Why do we need it?

Empathy is important because it helps us understand how others are feeling so we can respond appropriately to the situation. It is typically associated with social behaviour and there is lots of research showing that greater empathy leads to more helping behaviour.

However, this is not always the case. Empathy can also inhibit social actions, or even lead to amoral behaviour . For example, someone who sees a car accident and is overwhelmed by emotions witnessing the victim in severe pain might be less likely to help that person.

Similarly, strong empathetic feelings for members of our own family or our own social or racial group might lead to hate or aggression towards those we perceive as a threat. Think about a mother or father protecting their baby or a nationalist protecting their country.

People who are good at reading others’ emotions, such as manipulators, fortune-tellers or psychics, might also use their excellent empathetic skills for their own benefit by deceiving others.

empathy essay brainly

Interestingly, people with higher psychopathic traits typically show more utilitarian responses in moral dilemmas such as the footbridge problem. In this thought experiment, people have to decide whether to push a person off a bridge to stop a train about to kill five others laying on the track.

The psychopath would more often than not choose to push the person off the bridge. This is following the utilitarian philosophy that holds saving the life of five people by killing one person is a good thing. So one could argue those with psychopathic tendencies are more moral than normal people – who probably wouldn’t push the person off the bridge – as they are less influenced by emotions when making moral decisions.

How is empathy measured?

Empathy is often measured with self-report questionnaires such as the Interpersonal Reactivity Index (IRI) or Questionnaire for Cognitive and Affective Empathy (QCAE).

These typically ask people to indicate how much they agree with statements that measure different types of empathy.

The QCAE, for instance, has statements such as, “It affects me very much when one of my friends is upset”, which is a measure of affective empathy.

empathy essay brainly

Cognitive empathy is determined by the QCAE by putting value on a statement such as, “I try to look at everybody’s side of a disagreement before I make a decision.”

Using the QCAE, we recently found people who score higher on affective empathy have more grey matter, which is a collection of different types of nerve cells, in an area of the brain called the anterior insula.

This area is often involved in regulating positive and negative emotions by integrating environmental stimulants – such as seeing a car accident - with visceral and automatic bodily sensations.

We also found people who score higher on cognitive empathy had more grey matter in the dorsomedial prefrontal cortex.

This area is typically activated during more cognitive processes, such as Theory of Mind, which is the ability to attribute mental beliefs to yourself and another person. It also involves understanding that others have beliefs, desires, intentions, and perspectives different from one’s own.

Can empathy be selective?

Research shows we typically feel more empathy for members of our own group , such as those from our ethnic group. For example, one study scanned the brains of Chinese and Caucasian participants while they watched videos of members of their own ethnic group in pain. They also observed people from a different ethnic group in pain.

empathy essay brainly

The researchers found that a brain area called the anterior cingulate cortex, which is often active when we see others in pain, was less active when participants saw members of ethnic groups different from their own in pain.

Other studies have found brain areas involved in empathy are less active when watching people in pain who act unfairly . We even see activation in brain areas involved in subjective pleasure , such as the ventral striatum, when watching a rival sport team fail.

Yet, we do not always feel less empathy for those who aren’t members of our own group. In our recent study , students had to give monetary rewards or painful electrical shocks to students from the same or a different university. We scanned their brain responses when this happened.

Brain areas involved in rewarding others were more active when people rewarded members of their own group, but areas involved in harming others were equally active for both groups.

These results correspond to observations in daily life. We generally feel happier if our own group members win something, but we’re unlikely to harm others just because they belong to a different group, culture or race. In general, ingroup bias is more about ingroup love rather than outgroup hate.

empathy essay brainly

Yet in some situations, it could be helpful to feel less empathy for a particular group of people. For example, in war it might be beneficial to feel less empathy for people you are trying to kill, especially if they are also trying to harm you.

To investigate, we conducted another brain imaging study . We asked people to watch videos from a violent video game in which a person was shooting innocent civilians (unjustified violence) or enemy soldiers (justified violence).

While watching the videos, people had to pretend they were killing real people. We found the lateral orbitofrontal cortex, typically active when people harm others, was active when people shot innocent civilians. The more guilt participants felt about shooting civilians, the greater the response in this region.

However, the same area was not activated when people shot the soldier that was trying to kill them.

The results provide insight into how people regulate their emotions. They also show the brain mechanisms typically implicated when harming others become less active when the violence against a particular group is seen as justified.

This might provide future insights into how people become desensitised to violence or why some people feel more or less guilty about harming others.

Our empathetic brain has evolved to be highly adaptive to different types of situations. Having empathy is very useful as it often helps to understand others so we can help or deceive them, but sometimes we need to be able to switch off our empathetic feelings to protect our own lives, and those of others.

Tomorrow’s article will look at whether art can cultivate empathy.

  • Theory of mind
  • Emotional contagion
  • Understanding others' feelings

empathy essay brainly

Educational Designer

empathy essay brainly

Casual Facilitator: GERRIC Student Programs - Arts, Design and Architecture

empathy essay brainly

Senior Lecturer, Digital Advertising

empathy essay brainly

Associate Professor, Psychology

empathy essay brainly

Service Delivery Fleet Coordinator

  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Therapy Center
  • When To See a Therapist
  • Types of Therapy
  • Best Online Therapy
  • Best Couples Therapy
  • Managing Stress
  • Sleep and Dreaming
  • Understanding Emotions
  • Self-Improvement
  • Healthy Relationships
  • Student Resources
  • Personality Types
  • Sweepstakes
  • Guided Meditations
  • Verywell Mind Insights
  • 2024 Verywell Mind 25
  • Mental Health in the Classroom
  • Editorial Process
  • Meet Our Review Board
  • Crisis Support

What Is Empathy?

How it helps strengthen our relationships

Verywell / Bailey Mariner

  • Influential Factors
  • Lack of Empathy

Empathizing with others is essential for healthy relationships and communication. After all, it's hard to know how to relate to others if you can't understand their feelings.

Empathy is the ability to emotionally understand what other people feel, see things from their point of view, and imagine yourself in their place. Essentially, it is putting yourself in someone else's position and feeling what they are feeling.

The term empathy was first introduced in 1909 by psychologist Edward B. Titchener as a translation of the German term einfĂŒhlung (meaning "feeling into").

Empathy means that when you see another person suffering, such as after they've lost a loved one , you can envision yourself going through that same experience and feel what they are going through.

While people can be well-attuned to their feelings and emotions, getting into someone else's head can be more difficult. The ability to feel empathy allows people to "walk a mile in another's shoes," so to speak. It permits people to understand the emotions that others are feeling.

Press Play for Advice on Empathy

Hosted by therapist Amy Morin, LCSW, this episode of The Verywell Mind Podcast , featuring empathy expert Dr. Kelsey Crowe, shares how you can show empathy to someone who is going through a hard time. Click below to listen now.

Follow Now : Apple Podcasts / Spotify / Google Podcasts

Signs of Empathy

For many, seeing another person in pain and responding with indifference or even outright hostility seems utterly incomprehensible. But the fact that some people do respond in such a way clearly demonstrates that empathy is not necessarily a universal response to the suffering of others.

If you are wondering whether you are an empathetic person, here are some signs that show that you have this tendency:

  • You are good at really listening to what others have to say.
  • People often tell you about their problems.
  • You are good at picking up on how other people are feeling.
  • You often think about how other people feel.
  • Other people come to you for advice.
  • You often feel overwhelmed by tragic events.
  • You try to help others who are suffering.
  • You are good at telling when people aren't being honest .
  • You sometimes feel drained or overwhelmed in social situations.
  • You care deeply about other people.
  • You find it difficult to set boundaries in your relationships.

Are You an Empath? Take the Quiz!

Our fast and free empath quiz will let you know if your feelings and behaviors indicate high levels of traits commonly associated with empaths.

Types of Empathy

Empathy can come in different forms, depending on the situations. Some of the different types of empathy that you might experience are:

Affective Empathy

Affective empathy involves the ability to understand another person's emotions and respond appropriately. Such emotional understanding may lead to someone feeling concerned for another person's well-being, or it may lead to feelings of personal distress.

Somatic Empathy

Somatic empathy involves having a physical reaction in response to what someone else is experiencing. People sometimes physically experience what another person is feeling. When you see someone else feeling embarrassed, for example, you might start to blush or have an upset stomach.

Cognitive Empathy

Cognitive empathy involves being able to understand another person's mental state and what they might be thinking in response to the situation. This is related to what psychologists refer to as the theory of mind or thinking about what other people are thinking.

Empathy vs. Sympathy vs. Compassion

While sympathy and compassion are related to empathy, there are important differences. Compassion and sympathy are often thought to be more of a passive connection, while empathy generally involves a much more active attempt to understand another person.

The Many Benefits of Empathy

Being able to experience empathy has many beneficial uses. It's the ability that helps us see and feel what others might be experiencing. Because we relate to them, we can then respond in ways that foster stronger relationships.

It Strengthens your Relationships

Empathy allows you to build social connections with others. By understanding what people are thinking and feeling, you are able to respond appropriately in social situations. Research has shown that having social connections is important for both physical and psychological well-being.

It Helps You Regulate Your Emotions

Empathizing with others helps you learn to regulate your own emotions. Emotional regulation is important in that it allows you to manage what you are feeling, even in times of great stress, without becoming overwhelmed.

Research also suggests that our ability to regulate our own emotions influences how we respond to other people's emotions. Strengthening your self-regulation skills may be helpful if you want to boost your ability to empathize.

It Compels Us to Help Others

Empathy promotes helping behaviors. Not only are you more likely to engage in helpful behaviors when you feel empathy for other people, but other people are also more likely to help you when they experience empathy.

Research supports the idea that empathy is a key driver of prosocial behavior. Empathy helps us notice other people's needs, understand their distress, and inspire us to alleviate their suffering.

Impact of Empathy

Your ability to experience empathy can impact your relationships. Studies involving siblings have found that when empathy is high, siblings have less conflict and more warmth toward each other. In romantic relationships, having empathy increases your ability to extend forgiveness .

Can You Have Too Much Empathy?

Having a great deal of empathy makes you concerned for the well-being and happiness of others. It also means, however, that you can sometimes get overwhelmed, burned out , or even overstimulated from always thinking about other people's emotions. This can lead to empathy fatigue.

Empathy fatigue, also known as compassion fatigue , refers to the emotional and physical exhaustion you might feel after repeatedly being exposed to stressful or traumatic events . You might also feel numb or powerless, isolate yourself, and have a lack of energy.

Empathy fatigue is a concern in certain situations, such as when acting as a caregiver . Studies also show that if healthcare workers can't balance their feelings of empathy (affective empathy, in particular), it can result in compassion fatigue as well.

Other research has linked higher levels of empathy with a tendency toward emotional negativity , potentially increasing your risk of empathic distress. It can even affect your judgment, causing you to go against your morals based on the empathy you feel for someone else.

Factors That Can Influence Empathy

Not everyone experiences empathy in every situation. Some people may be more naturally empathetic in general, but people also tend to feel more empathetic toward some people and less so toward others. Some of the factors that play a role in this tendency include:

  • How you perceive the other person
  • How you attribute the other individual's behaviors
  • What you blame for the other person's predicament
  • Your past experiences and expectations

Research has found that there are gender differences in the experience and expression of empathy, although these findings are somewhat mixed. Women score higher on empathy tests, and studies suggest that women tend to feel more cognitive empathy than men. ï»ż ï»ż

At the most basic level, there appear to be two main factors that contribute to the ability to experience empathy: genetics and socialization. Essentially, it boils down to the age-old relative contributions of nature and nurture .

Parents pass down genes that contribute to overall personality, including the propensity toward sympathy, empathy, and compassion. For example, research indicates that key traits known as the Big Five personality traits are between 31% and 41% heritable. Being high in traits like conscientiousness and agreeableness can contribute to increased feelings of empathy for others.

On the other hand, people are also socialized by their parents, peers, communities, and society. How people treat others and how they feel about others often reflect the beliefs and values that were instilled at a very young age. 

Reasons People Sometimes Lack Empathy

Some people lack empathy and, therefore, aren't able to understand what another person may be experiencing or feeling. This can result in behaviors that seem uncaring or sometimes even hurtful. For instance, people with low affective empathy have higher rates of cyberbullying .

A lack of empathy is also one of the defining characteristics of narcissistic personality disorder . Though, it is unclear whether this is due to a person with this disorder having no empathy at all or having more of a dysfunctional response to others.

A few reasons why people sometimes lack empathy include cognitive biases, dehumanization, and victim-blaming.

Cognitive Biases

Sometimes the way people perceive the world around them is influenced by cognitive biases . For example, people often attribute other people's failures to internal characteristics, while blaming their own shortcomings on external factors.

These biases can make it difficult to see all the factors that contribute to a situation. They also make it less likely that people will be able to see a situation from the perspective of another.

Dehumanization

Many also fall into the trap of thinking that people who are different from them don't feel and behave the same as they do. This is particularly common when other people are physically distant.

Othering is a way of excluding people from the in-group, which can then contribute to dehumanization. For example, when they watch reports of a disaster or conflict in a foreign land, people might be less likely to feel empathy if they think those suffering are fundamentally different from themselves.

Victim Blaming

Sometimes, when another person has suffered a terrible experience, people make the mistake of blaming the victim for their circumstances. This is the reason that victims of crimes are often asked what they might have done differently to prevent the crime.

This tendency stems from the need to believe that the world is a fair and just place. It is the desire to believe that people get what they deserve and deserve what they get—and it can fool you into thinking that such terrible things could never happen to you.

What Causes Empathy?

Human beings are certainly capable of selfish, even cruel, behavior. A quick scan of the news quickly reveals numerous unkind, selfish, and heinous actions. The question, then, is why don't we all engage in such self-serving behavior all the time? What is it that causes us to feel another's pain and respond with kindness ?

Several different theories have been proposed to explain why people experience empathy.

Neuroscientific Explanations

Studies have shown that specific areas of the brain play a role in how empathy is experienced. More recent approaches focus on the cognitive and neurological processes that lie behind empathy. Researchers have found that different regions of the brain play an important role in empathy, including the anterior cingulate cortex and the anterior insula.

Research suggests that there are important neurobiological components to the experience of empathy. ï»ż ï»ż The activation of mirror neurons in the brain plays a part in the ability to mirror and mimic the emotional responses that people would feel if they were in similar situations.

Functional MRI research also indicates that an area of the brain known as the inferior frontal gyrus (IFG) plays a critical role in the experience of empathy. Studies have found that people who have damage to this area of the brain often have difficulty recognizing emotions conveyed through facial expressions .  

Emotional Explanations

Some of the earliest explorations into the topic of empathy centered on how feeling what others feel allows people to have a variety of emotional experiences. The philosopher Adam Smith suggested that it allows us to experience things that we might never otherwise be able to fully feel.

This can involve feeling empathy for both real people and imaginary characters. Experiencing empathy for fictional characters allows people to have a range of emotional experiences that might otherwise be impossible.

Prosocial Explanations

Sociologist Herbert Spencer proposed that empathy served an adaptive function and aided in the survival of the species. Empathy leads to helping behavior, which benefits social relationships. Humans are naturally social creatures. Things that aid in our relationships with other people benefit us as well.

When people experience empathy, they are more likely to engage in prosocial behaviors that benefit other people. Things such as altruism and heroism are also connected to feeling empathy for others.

Tips for Practicing Empathy

Fortunately, empathy is a skill that you can learn and strengthen. If you would like to build your empathy skills, there are a few things that you can do:

  • Work on listening to people without interrupting and utilize empathic listening
  • Pay attention to body language and other types of nonverbal communication
  • Try to understand people, even when you don't agree with them
  • Ask people questions to learn more about them and their lives
  • Imagine yourself in another person's shoes
  • Strengthen your connection with others to learn more about how they feel
  • Seek to identify biases you may have and how they affect your empathy for others
  • Look for ways in which you are similar to others versus focusing on differences
  • Be willing to be vulnerable , opening up about how you feel
  • Engage in new experiences, giving you better insight into how others in that situation may feel
  • Get involved in organizations that push for social change

While empathy might be lacking in some, most people are able to empathize with others in a variety of situations. This ability to see things from another person's perspective and empathize with another's emotions plays an important role in our social lives. Empathy allows us to understand others and, quite often, compels us to take action to relieve another person's suffering.

Harandi TF, Taghinasab MM, Nayeri TD. The correlation of social support with mental health: A meta-analysis .  Electron Physician . 2017;9(9):5212-5222. doi:10.19082/5212

Thompson NM, Uusberg A, Gross JJ, Chakrabarti B. Empathy and emotion regulation: An integrative account .  Prog Brain Res . 2019;247:273-304. doi:10.1016/bs.pbr.2019.03.024

Decety J, Bartal IB, Uzefovsky F, Knafo-Noam A. Empathy as a driver of prosocial behaviour: Highly conserved neurobehavioural mechanisms across species .  Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci . 2016;371(1686):20150077. doi:10.1098/rstb.2015.0077

Lam CB, Solmeyer AR, McHale SM. Sibling relationships and empathy across the transition to adolescence . J Youth Adolescen . 2012;41:1657-1670. doi:10.1007/s10964-012-9781-8

Kimmes JG, Durtschi JA. Forgiveness in romantic relationships: The roles of attachment, empathy, and attributions . J Marital Family Ther . 2016;42(4):645-658. doi:10.1111/jmft.12171

Cleveland Clinic. Empathy fatigue: How stress and trauma can take a toll on you .

Duarte J, Pinto-Bouveia J, Cruz B. Relationships between nurses' empathy, self-compassion and dimensions of professional quality of life: A cross-sectional study . Int J Nursing Stud . 2016;60:1-11. doi:10.1016/j.ijnurstu.2016.02.015

Chikovani G, Babuadze L, Iashvili N, Gvalia T, Surguladze S. Empathy costs: Negative emotional bias in high empathisers . Psychiatry Res . 2015;229(1-2):340-346. doi:10.1016/j.psychres.2015.07.001

Kret ME, De Gelder B. A review on sex difference in processing emotional signals . Neuropsychologia . 2012; 50(7):1211-1221. doi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2011.12.022

Sanchez-Roige S, Gray JC, MacKillop J, Chen CH, Palmer AA. The genetics of human personality .  Genes Brain Behav . 2018;17(3):e12439. doi:10.1111/gbb.12439

Song Y, Shi M. Associations between empathy and big five personality traits among Chinese undergraduate medical students .  PLoS One . 2017;12(2):e0171665. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0171665

Schultze-Krumbholz A, Scheithauer H. Is cyberbullying related to lack of empathy and social-emotional problems? Int J Develop Sci . 2013;7(3-4):161-166. doi:10.3233/DEV-130124

Baskin-Sommers A, Krusemark E, Ronningstam E. Empathy in narcissistic personality disorder: From clinical and empirical perspectives . Personal Dis Theory Res Treat . 2014;5(3):323-333. doi:10.1037/per0000061

Decety, J. Dissecting the neural mechanisms mediating empathy . Emotion Review . 2011; 3(1): 92-108. doi:10.1177/1754073910374662

Shamay-Tsoory SG, Aharon-Peretz J, Perry D. Two systems for empathy: A double dissociation between emotional and cognitive empathy in inferior frontal gyrus versus ventromedial prefrontal lesions . Brain . 2009;132(PT3): 617-627. doi:10.1093/brain/awn279

Hillis AE. Inability to empathize: Brain lesions that disrupt sharing and understanding another's emotions . Brain . 2014;137(4):981-997. doi:10.1093/brain/awt317

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Adam Smith's moral and political philosophy .

By Kendra Cherry, MSEd Kendra Cherry, MS, is a psychosocial rehabilitation specialist, psychology educator, and author of the "Everything Psychology Book."

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

The concept of empathy is used to refer to a wide range of psychological capacities that are thought of as being central for constituting humans as social creatures allowing us to know what other people are thinking and feeling, to emotionally engage with them, to share their thoughts and feelings, and to care for their well–being. Ever since the eighteenth century, due particularly to the influence of the writings of David Hume and Adam Smith, those capacities have been at the center of scholarly investigations into the underlying psychological basis of our social and moral nature. Yet, the concept of empathy is of relatively recent intellectual heritage. Moreover, since researchers in different disciplines have focused their investigations on very specific aspects of the broad range of empathy-related phenomena, one should probably not be surprised by a certain amount of conceptual confusion and a multiplicity of definitions associated with the empathy concept in a number of different scientific and non-scientific discourses. The purpose of this entry is to clarify the empathy concept by surveying its history in various philosophical and psychological discussions and by indicating why empathy was and should be regarded to be of such central importance in understanding human agency in ordinary contexts, in the human sciences, and for the constitution of ourselves as social and moral agents. More specifically, after a short historical introduction articulating the philosophical context within which the empathy concept was coined, the second and third sections will discuss the epistemic dimensions associated with our empathic capacities. They will address the contention that empathy is the primary epistemic means for knowing other minds and that it should be viewed as the unique method distinguishing the human from the natural sciences. Sections 4 and 5 will then focus on claims that view empathy as the fundamental social glue and that understand empathy as the main psychological mechanism enabling us to establish and maintain social relations and taking an evaluative stance towards each other.

1. Historical Introduction

2.1 mirror neurons, simulation, and the discussion of empathy in the contemporary theory of mind debate, 3.1 the critique of empathy in the context of a hermeneutic conception of the human sciences, 3.2 the critique of empathy within the context of a naturalist conception of the human sciences, 4. empathy as a topic of scientific exploration in psychology, 5.1 empathy and altruistic motivation, 5.2 empathy, its partiality, susceptibility to bias, and moral agency, 5.3 empathy, moral judgment, and the authority of moral norms, other internet resources, related entries.

Before the psychologist Edward Titchener (1867–1927) introduced the term “empathy” in 1909 into the English language as the translation of the German term “Einfühlung” (or “feeling into”), “sympathy”was the term commonly used to refer to empathy-related phenomena. If one were to point to a conceptual core for understanding these phenomena, it is probably best to point to David Hume’s dictum that “the minds of men are mirrors to one another,”(Hume 1739–40 [1978], 365) since in encountering other persons, humans can resonate with and recreate that person’s thoughts and emotions on different dimensions of cognitive complexity. While, as we will see, not everybody shares such resonance conception of empathy(some philosophers in the phenomenological tradition emphatically reject it), it certainly constitutes the center of Theodor Lipps’s understanding, who Titchener had in mind in his translation of “Einfühlung” as “empathy.”

Theodor Lipps (1851–1914)was also very familiar with the work of David Hume (see the introduction to Coplan and Goldie 2011 in this respect). More importantly, it was Theodor Lipps, whose work transformed empathy/Einfühlung from a concept of nineteenth century German aesthetics into a central category of the philosophy of the social and human sciences. To understand this transformation we first need to appreciate the reasons why philosophers of the nineteenth century thought it necessary to appeal to empathy in order to account for our ability to appreciate natural objects and artefacts in an aesthetic manner. According to the dominant (even though not universally accepted) positivistic and empiricist conception, sense data constitute the fundamental basis for our investigation of the world. Yet from a phenomenological perspective, our perceptual encounter with aesthetic objects and our appreciation of them as being beautiful—our admiration of a beautiful sunset, for example—seems to be as direct as our perception of an object as being red or square. By appealing to the psychological mechanisms of empathy, philosophers intended to provide an explanatory account of the phenomenological immediacy of our aesthetic appreciation of objects. More specifically, for Lipps, our empathic encounter with external objects trigger inner “processes” that give rise to experiences similar to ones that I have when I engage in various activities involving the movement of my body. Since my attention is perceptually focused on the external object, I experience them—or I automatically project my experiences—as being in the object. If those experiences are in some way apprehended in a positive manner and as being in some sense life-affirming, I perceive the object as beautiful, otherwise as ugly. In the first case, Lipps speaks of positive; in the later of negative empathy. Lipps also characterizes our experience of beauty as “objectified self-enjoyment,” since we are impressed by the “vitality” and “life potentiality” that lies in the perceived object (Lipps 1906, 1903 a,b. For the contemporary discussion of empathy’s role in aesthetics see particularly Breithaupt 2009; Coplan and Goldie 2011 (Part II); Curtis & Koch 2009; and Keen 2007. For a recent history of the empathy concept see also Lanzoni 2018).

In his Aesthetik, Lipps closely links our aesthetic perception and our perception of another embodied person as a minded creature. The nature of aesthetic empathy is always the “experience of another human” (1905, 49) . We appreciate another object as beautiful because empathy allows us to see it in analogy to another human body. Similarly, we recognize another organism as a minded creature because of empathy. Empathy in this context is more specifically understood as a phenomenon of “inner imitation,” where my mind mirrors the mental activities or experiences of another person based on the observation of his bodily activities or facial expressions. Empathy is ultimately based on an innate disposition for motor mimicry, a fact that is well established in the psychological literature and was already noticed by Adam Smith (1853). Even though such a disposition is not always externally manifested, Lipps suggests that it is always present as an inner tendency giving rise to similar kinaesthetic sensations in the observer as felt by the observed target. In seeing the angry face of another person we instinctually have a tendency of imitating it and of “imitating” her anger in this manner. Since we are not aware of such tendencies, we see the anger in her face (Lipps 1907). Despite the fact that Lipps’s primary examples of empathy focus on the recognition of emotions expressed in bodily gestures or facial expressions, his conception of empathy should not be understood as being limited to such cases. As his remarks about intellectual empathy suggest (1903b/05), he regards our recognition of all mental activities—insofar as they are activities requiring human effort—as being based on empathy or on inner imitation (See also the introductory chapter in Stueber 2006).

2. Empathy and the Philosophical Problem of Other Minds

It was indeed Lipps’s claim that empathy should be understood as the primary epistemic means for gaining knowledge of other minds that was the focus of a lively debate among philosophers at the beginning of the 20 th century (Prandtl 1910, Stein 1917, Scheler 1973). Even philosophers, who did not agree with Lipps’s specific explication, found the concept of empathy appealing because his argument for his position was closely tied to a thorough critique of what was widely seen at that time as the only alternative for conceiving of knowledge of other minds, that is, Mill’s inference from analogy. Traditionally, the inference from analogy presupposes a Cartesian conception of the mind according to which access to our own mind is direct and infallible, whereas knowledge of other minds is inferential, fallible, and based on evidence about other persons’ observed physical behavior. More formally one can characterize the inference from analogy as consisting of the following premises or steps.

i.) Another person X manifests behavior of type B . ii.) In my own case behavior of type B is caused by mental state of type M . iii.) Since my and X ’s outward behavior of type B is similar, it has to have similar inner mental causes. (It is thus assumed that I and the other persons are psychologically similar in the relevant sense.) Therefore: The other person’s behavior ( X ’s behavior) is caused by a mental state of type M .

Like Wittgenstein, but predating him considerably, Lipps argues in his 1907 article “Das Wissen von fremden Ichen” that the inference from analogy falls fundamentally short of solving the philosophical problem of other minds. Lipps does not argue against the inference from analogy because of its evidentially slim basis, but because it does not allow us to understand its basic presupposition that another person has a mind that is psychologically similar to our own mind. The inference from analogy thus cannot be understood as providing us with evidence for the claim that the other person has mental states like we do because, within its Cartesian framework, we are unable to conceive of other minds in the first place. For Lipps, analogical reasoning requires the contradictory undertaking of inferring another person’s anger and sadness on the basis of my sadness and anger, yet to think of that sadness and anger simultaneously as something “absolutely different” from my anger and sadness. More generally, analogical inference is a contradictory undertaking because it entails “entertaining a completely new thought about an I, that however is not me, but something absolutely different” (Lipps 1907, 708, my translation).

Yet while Lipps diagnoses the problem of the inference of analogy within the context of a Cartesian conception of the mind quite succinctly, he fails to explain how empathy is able to provide us with an epistemically sanctioned understanding of other minds or why our “feeling into” the other person’s mind is more than a mere projection. More importantly, Lipps does not sufficiently explain why empathy does not encounter similar problems to the ones diagnosed for the inference from analogy and how empathy allows us to conceive of other persons as having a mind similar to our own if we are directly acquainted only with our own mental states(See Stueber 2006). Wittgenstein’s critique of the inference from analogy is in the end more penetrating because he recognizes that its problem depends on a Cartesian account of mental concepts. If my grasp of a mental concept is exclusively constituted by me experiencing something in a certain way, then it is impossible for me to conceive of how that very same concept can be applied to somebody else, given that I cannot experience somebody else’s mental states. I therefore cannot conceive of how another person can be in the same mental state as I am because that would require that I can conceive of my mental state as something, which I do not experience. But according to the Cartesian conception this seems to be a conceptually impossible task. Moreover, if one holds on to a Cartesian conception of the mind, it is not clear how appealing to empathy, as conceived of by Lipps, should help us in conceiving of mental states as belonging to another mind.

Within the phenomenological tradition, the above shortcomings of Lipps’s position of empathy were quite apparent (see for example Stein 1917, 24 and Scheler 1973, 236). Yet despite the fact that they did not accept Lipps’s explication of empathy as being based on mechanisms of inner resonance and projection, authors within the phenomenological tradition of philosophy were persuaded by Lipps’s critique of the inference from analogy. For that very reason, Husserl and Stein, for example, continued using the concept of empathy and regarded empathy as an irreducible “type of experiential act sui generis” (Stein 1917, 10), which allows us to view another person as being analogous to ourselves without this “analogizing apprehension” constituting an inference of analogy (Husserl 1931 [1963], 141). Scheler went probably the furthest in rejecting the Cartesian framework in thinking about the apprehension of other minds, while keeping committed to something like the concept of empathy. [ 1 ] (In order to contrast his position from Lipps, Scheler however preferred to use the term “nachfühlen” rather than “einfühlen.”) For Scheler, the fundamental mistake of the debate about the apprehension of other minds consists in the fact that it does not take seriously certain phenomenological facts. Prima facie, we do not encounter merely the bodily movements of another person. Rather, we are directly recognizing specific mental states because they are characteristically expressed in states of the human body; in facial expressions, in gestures, in the tone of voice, and so on. Empathy within the phenomenological tradition then is not conceived of as a resonance phenomenon requiring the observer to recreate the mental states of the other person in his or her own mind but as a special perceptual act (See Scheler 1973, particularly 232–258; For a succinct explication of the debate about empathy in the phenomenological tradition consult Zahavi 2010)

The idea that empathy understood as inner imitation is the primary epistemic means for understanding other minds has however been revived in the 1980’s by simulation theorists in the context of the interdisciplinary debate about folk psychology; an empirically informed debate about how best to describe the underlying causal mechanisms of our folk psychological abilities to interpret, explain, and predict other agents. (See Davies and Stone 1995). In contrast to theory theory, simulation theorists conceive of our ordinary mindreading abilities as an ego-centric method and as a “knowledge–poor” strategy, where I do not utilize a folk psychological theory but use myself as a model for the other person’s mental life. It is not the place here to discuss the contemporary debate extensively, but it has to be emphasized that contemporary simulation theorists vigorously discuss how to account for our grasp of mental concepts and whether simulation theory is committed to Cartesianism. Whereas Goldman (2002, 2006) links his version of simulation theory to a neo-Cartesian account of mental concepts, other simulation theorists develop versions of simulation theory that are not committed to a Cartesian conception of the mind. (Gordon 1995a, b, and 2000; Heal 2003; and Stueber 2006, 2012).

Moreover, neuroscientific findings according to which so called mirror neurons play an important role in recognizing another person’s emotional states and in understanding the goal-directedness of his behavior have been understood as providing empirical evidence for Lipps’ idea of empathy as inner imitation. With the help of the term “mirror neuron,” scientists refer to the fact that there is significant overlap between neural areas of excitation that underlie our observation of another person’s action and areas that are stimulated when we execute the very same action. A similar overlap between neural areas of excitation has also been established for our recognition of another person’s emotion based on his facial expression and our experiencing the emotion. (For a survey on mirror neurons see Gallese 2003a and b, Goldman 2006, chap. 6; Keysers 2011; Rizzolatti and Craighero 2004; and particularly Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2008). Since the face to face encounter between persons is the primary situation within which human beings recognize themselves as minded creatures and attribute mental states to others, the system of mirror neurons has been interpreted as playing a causally central role in establishing intersubjective relations between minded creatures. For that very reason, the neuroscientist Gallese thinks of mirror neurons as constituting what he calls the “shared manifold of intersubjectivity” (Gallese 2001, 44). Stueber (2006, chap. 4)—inspired by Lipps’s conception of empathy as inner imitation—refers to mirror neurons as mechanisms of basic empathy; [ 2 ] as mechanisms that allow us to apprehend directly another person’s emotions in light of his facial expressions and that enable us to understand his bodily movements as goal-directed actions, that is, as being directed towards an external object like a person reaching for the cup. The evidence from mirror neurons—and the fact that in perceiving other people we use very different neurobiological mechanisms than in the perception of physical objects—does suggest that in our primary perceptual encounter with the world we do not merely encounter physical objects. Rather, even on this basic level, we distinguish already between mere physical objects and objects that are more like us (See also Meltzoff and Brooks 2001). The mechanisms of basic empathy have to be seen as Nature’s way of dissolving one of the principal assumptions of the traditional philosophical discussion about other minds shared by opposing positions such as Cartesianism and Behaviorism; that is, that we perceive other people primarily as physical objects and do not distinguish already on the perceptual level between physical objects like trees and minded creatures like ourselves. Mechanisms of basic empathy might therefore be interpreted as providing us with a perceptual and non-conceptual basis for developing an intersubjectively accessible folk psychological framework that is applicable to the subject and observed other (Stueber 2006, 142–45).

It needs to be acknowledged however that this interpretation of mirror neurons crucially depends on the assumption that the primary function of mirror neurons consists in providing us with a cognitive grasp of another person’s actions and emotions. This interpretation has however been criticized by researchers and philosophers who think that neural resonance presupposes rather than provides us with an understanding of what is going on in the minds of others (Csibra 2007, Hickok 2008 and 2014). They have also pointed out that in observing another person’s emotion or behavior, we never fully “mirror” another person’s neural stimulation. The neuroscientist Jean Decety has argued that in observing another person’s pain our vicariously stimulated pain matrix is not sensitive to the phenomenal quality of pain. Rather it is sensitive to pain as an indicator of “aversion and withdrawal when exposed to danger and threats”(Decety and Cowell 2015, 6 and Decety 2010). At least as far as empathy for pain is concerned, our neural resonance is also modulated by a variety of contextual factors, such as how close we feel to the observed subject, whether we regard the pain to be morally justified (as in the case of punishment, for example) or whether we regard it as unavoidable and necessary, such as in a medical procedure (Singer and Lamm 2009; but see also Allen 2010, Borg 2007, Debes 2010, Gallese 2016, Goldman 2009, Iacoboni 2011, Jacob 2008, Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2016, and Stueber 2012a).

Yet it should be noted that everyday mindreading is not restricted to the realm of basic empathy. Ordinarily we not only recognize that other persons are afraid or that they are reaching for a particular object. We understand their behavior in more complex social contexts in terms of their reasons for acting using the full range of psychological concepts including the concepts of belief and desire. Evidence from neuroscience shows that these mentalizing tasks involve very different neuronal areas such as the medial prefrontal cortex, temporoparietal cortex, and the cingulate cortex. (For a survey see Kain and Perner 2003; Frith and Frith 2003; Zaki and Ochsner 2012). Low level mindreading in the realm of basic empathy has therefore to be distinguished from higher levels of mindreading (Goldman 2006). It is clear that low level forms of understanding other persons have to be conceived of as being relatively knowledge– poor as they do not involve a psychological theory or complex psychological concepts. How exactly one should conceive of high level mindreading abilities, whether they involve primarily knowledge–poor simulation strategies or knowledge–rich inferences is controversially debated within the contemporary debate about our folk psychological mindreading abilities(See Davies and Stone 1995, Gopnik and Meltzoff 1997, Gordon 1995, Currie and Ravenscroft 2002, Heal 2003, Nichols and Stich 2003, Goldman 2006, and Stueber 2006). Simulation theorists, however, insist that even more complex forms of understanding other agents involve resonance phenomena that engage our cognitively intricate capacities of imaginatively adopting the perspective of another person and reenacting or recreating their thought processes (For various forms of perspective-taking see Coplan 2011 and Goldie 2000). Accordingly, simulation theorists distinguish between different types of empathy such as between basic and reenactive empathy (Stueber 2006) or between mirroring and reconstructive empathy (Goldman 2011). Interestingly, the debate about how to conceive of these more complex forms of mindreading resonates with the traditional debate about whether empathy is the unique method of the human sciences and whether or not one has to strictly distinguish between the methods of the human and the natural sciences. Equally noteworthy is the fact that in the contemporary theory of mind debate voices have grown louder that assert that the contemporary theory of mind debate fundamentally misconceives of the nature of social cognition. In light of insights from the phenomenological and hermeneutic traditions in philosophy, they claim that on the most basic level empathy should not be conceived of as a resonance phenomenon but as a type of direct perception. (See particularly Zahavi 2010; Zahavi and Overgaard 2012, but Jacob 2011 for a response). More complex forms of social cognition are also not to be understood as being based on either theory or empathy/simulation, rather they are better best conceived of as the ability to directly fit observed units of actions into larger narrative or cultural frameworks (For this debate see Gallagher 2012, Gallagher and Hutto 2008, Hutto 2008, and Seemann 2011, Stueber 2011 and 2012a, and various articles in Matravers and Waldow 2018). For skepticism about empathic perspective-taking understood as a complete identification with the perspective of the other person see also Goldie 2011). Regardless of how one views this specific debate it should be clear that ideas about mindreading developed originally by proponents of empathy at the beginning of the 20 th century can no longer be easily dismissed and have to be taken seriously.

3. Empathy as the Unique Method of the Human Sciences

At the beginning of the 20 th century, empathy understood as a non-inferential and non-theoretical method of grasping the content of other minds became closely associated with the concept of understanding (Verstehen); a concept that was championed by the hermeneutic tradition of philosophy concerned with explicating the methods used in grasping the meaning and significance of texts, works of arts, and actions. (For a survey of this tradition see Grondin 1994). Hermeneutic thinkers insisted that the method used in understanding the significance of a text or a historical event has to be fundamentally distinguished from the method used in explaining an event within the context of the natural sciences. This methodological dualism is famously expressed by Droysen in saying that “historical research does not want to explain; that is, derive in a form of an inferential argument, rather it wants to understand” (Droysen 1977, 403), and similarly in Dilthey’s dictum that “we explain nature, but understand the life of the soul” (Dilthey 1961, vol. 5, 144). Yet Droysen and authors before him never conceived of understanding solely as an act of mental imitation or solely as an act of imaginatively “transporting” oneself into the point of view of another person. Such “psychological interpretation” as Schleiermacher (1998) used to call it, was conceived of as constituting only one aspect of the interpretive method used by historians. Other tasks mentioned in this context involved critically evaluating the reliability of historical sources, getting to know the linguistic conventions of a language, and integrating the various elements derived from historical sources into a consistent narrative of a particular epoch. The differences between these various aspects of the interpretive procedure were however downplayed in the early Dilthey. For him, grasping the significance of any cultural fact had to be understood as a mental act of “transposition.” (See for example Dilthey 1961, vol. 5, 263–265). .

Ironically, the close association of the concepts of empathy and understanding and the associated claim that empathy is the sole and unique method of the human sciences also facilitated the decline of the empathy concept and its almost utter disregard by philosophers of the human and social sciences later on, in both the analytic and continental/hermeneutic traditions of philosophy. Within both traditions, proponents of empathy were—for very different reasons—generally seen as advocating an epistemically naïve and insufficiently broad conception of the methodological proceedings in the human sciences. As a result, most philosophers of the human and social sciences maintained their distance from the idea that empathy is central for our understanding of other minds and mental phenomena. Notable exceptions in this respect are R.G. Collingwood and his followers, who suggested that reenacting another person’s thoughts is necessary for understanding them as rational agents (Collingwood 1946, Dray 1957 and 1995). Notice however that in contrast to the contemporary debate about folk psychology, the debate about empathy in the philosophy of social science is not concerned with investigating underlying causal mechanisms. Rather, it addresses normative questions of how to justify a particular explanation or interpretation.

Philosophers arguing for a hermeneutic conception of the human and social sciences insist on a strict methodological division between the human and the natural sciences. [ 3 ] Yet they nowadays favor the concept of understanding (Verstehen) and reject the earlier identification of understanding and empathy for two specific reasons. First, empathy is no longer seen as the unique method of the human sciences because facts of significance, which a historian or an interpreter of literary and non-literary texts are interested in, do not solely depend on facts within the individual mind. A historian, for example, is not bound by the agent’s perspective in telling the story of a particular historical time period(Danto 1965). Similarly, philosophers such as Hans Georg Gadamer, have argued that the significance of a text is not tied to the author’s intentions in writing the text. In reading a text by Shakespeare or Plato we are not primarily interested in finding out what Plato or Shakespeare said but what these texts themselves say.(Gadamer 1989; for a critical discussion see Skinner (in Tully 1988); “Introduction” in Kögler and Stueber 2000; and Stueber 2002).

The above considerations, however, do not justify the claim that empathy has no role to play within the context of the human sciences. It justifies merely the claim that empathy cannot be their only method, at least as long as one admits that recognizing the thoughts of individual agents has to play some role in the interpretive project of the human sciences. Accordingly, a second reason against empathy is also emphasized. Conceiving of understanding other agents as being based on empathy is seen as an epistemically extremely naïve conception of the interpretation of individual agents, since it seems to conceive of understanding as a mysterious meeting of two individual minds outside of any cultural context. Individual agents are always socially and culturally embedded creatures. Understanding other agents thus presupposes an understanding of the cultural context within which an agent functions. Moreover, in the interpretive situation of the human sciences, the cultural background of the interpreter and the person, who has to be interpreted, can be very different. In that case, I can not very easily put myself in the shoes of the other person and imitate his thoughts in my mind. If understanding medieval knights, to use an example of Winch (1958), requires me to think exactly as the medieval knight did, then it is not clear how such a task can be accomplished from an interpretive perspective constituted by very different cultural presuppositions. Making sense of other minds has, therefore, to be seen as an activity that is a culturally mediated one; a fact that empathy theorists according to this line of critique do not sufficiently take into account when they conceive of understanding other agents as a direct meeting of minds that is independent of and unaided by information about how these agents are embedded in a broader social environment. (See Stueber 2006, chap.6, Zahavi 2001, 2005; for the later Dilthey see Makreel 2000. For a critical discussion of whether the concept of understanding without recourse to empathy is useful for marking an epistemic distinction between the human and natural sciences consult also Stueber 2012b. Within the context of anthropology, Hollan and Throop argue that empathy is best understood as a dynamic, culturally situated, temporally extended, and dialogical process actively involving not only the interpreter but also his or her interpretee. See Hollan 20012; Hollan and Throop 2008, 2001; Throop 2010).).

Philosophers, who reject the methodological dualism between the human and the natural sciences as argued for in the hermeneutic context, are commonly referred to as naturalists in the philosophy of social science. They deny that the distinction between understanding and explanation points to an important methodological difference. Even in the human or social sciences, the main point of the scientific endeavor is to provide epistemically justified explanations (and predictions) of observed or recorded events (see also Henderson 1993). At most, empathy is granted a heuristic role in the context of discovery. It however can not play any role within the context of justification. As particularly Hempel (1965) has argued, to explain an event involves—at least implicitly—an appeal to law-like regularities providing us with reasons for expecting that an event of a certain kind will occur under specific circumstances. Empathy might allow me to recognize that I would have acted in the same manner as somebody else. Yet it does not epistemically sanction the claim that anybody of a particular type or anybody who is in that type of situation will act in this manner.

Hempel’s argument against empathy has certainly not gone unchallenged. Within the philosophy of history, Dray (1957), following Collingwood, has argued that empathy plays an epistemically irreducible role, since we explain actions in terms of an agent’s reasons. For him, such reason explanations do not appeal to empirical generalizations but to normative principles of actions outlining how a person should act in a particular situation. Similar arguments have been articulated by Jaegwon Kim (1984, 1998). Yet as Stueber (2006, chap. 5) argues such a response to Hempel would require us to implausibly conceive of reason explanations as being very different from ordinary causal explanations. It would imply that our notions of explanation and causation are ambiguous concepts. Reasons that cause agents to act in the physical world would be conceived of as causes in a very different sense than ordinary physical causes. Moreover, as Hempel himself suggests, appealing to normative principles explains at most why a person should have acted in a certain manner. It does not explain why he ultimately acted in that way. Consequently, Hempel’s objection against empathy retain their force as long as one maintains that reason explanations are a form of ordinary causal explanations and as long as one conceives of the epistemic justification of such explanations as implicitly appealing to some empirical generalizations (For Kim’s recent attempt to account for the explanatory character of action explanations by acknowledging the centrality of the first person perspective see also Kim 2010).

Despite these concessions to Hempel, Stueber suggests that empathy (specifically reenactive empathy) has to be acknowledged as playing a central role even in the context of justification. For him, folk psychological explanations have to be understood as being tied to the domain of rational agency. In contrast to explanations in terms of mere inner causes, folk psychological explanations retain their explanatory force only as long as agents’ beliefs and desires can also be understood as reasons for their actions. The epistemic justification of such folk psychological explanations implicitly relies on generalizations involving folk psychological notions such as belief and desire. Yet the existence of such generalizations alone does not establish specific beliefs and desires as reasons for a person’s actions. Elaborating on considerations by Heal (2003) and Collingwood (1946), Stueber suggests that recognizing beliefs and desires as reasons requires the interpreter to be sensitive to an agent’s other relevant beliefs and desires. Individual thoughts function as reasons for rational agency only relative to a specific framework of an agent’s thoughts that are relevant for consideration in a specific situation. Most plausibly—given our persistent inability to solve the frame problem—recognizing which of another agent’s thoughts are relevant in specific contexts requires the practical ability of reenacting another person’s thoughts in one’s own mind. Empathy’s central epistemic role has to be admitted, since beliefs and desires can be understood only in this manner as an agent’s reasons (See Stueber 2006, 2008, 2013. For a related discussion about the role of understanding in contemporary epistemology and philosophy of science see Grimm 2016 and Grimm, Baumberger, and Ammon 2017).

The discussion of empathy within psychology has been largely unaffected by the critical philosophical discussion of empathy as an epistemic means to know other minds or as the unique method of the human sciences. Rather, psychologists’ interest in empathy–related phenomena harks back to eighteenth century moral philosophy, particularly David Hume and Adam Smith (See also Wispe 1991). Here empathy, or what was then called sympathy, was regarded to play a central role in constituting human beings as social and moral creatures allowing us to emotionally connect to our human companions and care for their well-being. Throughout the early 20 th century, but particularly since the late 1940’s, empathy has, therefore, been an intensively studied topic of psychological research.

More broadly one can distinguish two psychological research traditions studying empathy–related phenomena; that is, the study of what is currently called empathic accuracy and the study of empathy as an emotional phenomenon in the encounter of others. The first area of study defines empathy primarily as a cognitive phenomenon and conceives of empathy in general terms as “the intellectual or imaginative apprehension of another’s condition or state of mind,” to use Hogan’s (1969) terminology. Within this area of research, one is primarily interested in determining the reliability and accuracy of our ability to perceive and recognize other persons’ enduring personality traits, attitudes and values, and occurrent mental states. One also investigates the various factors that influence empathic accuracy. One has, for example, been interested in determining whether empathic ability depends on gender, age, family background, intelligence, emotional stability, the nature of interpersonal relations, or whether it depends on specific motivations of the observer. (For a survey see Ickes 1993 and 2003; and Taft 1955). A more detailed account of the research on empathic accuracy and some of its earlier methodological difficulties can be found in the

Supplementary document on the Study of Cognitive Empathy and Empathic Accuracy .

Philosophically more influential has been the study of empathy defined primarily as an emotional or affective phenomenon, which psychologists in the middle of the 1950’s started to focus on. In this context, psychologists have also addressed issues of moral motivation that have been traditionally topics of intense discussions among moral philosophers. They were particularly interested in investigating (i) the development of various means for measuring empathy as a dispositional trait of adults and of children and as a situational response in specific situations, (ii) the factors on which empathic responses and dispositions depend, and (iii) the relation between empathy and pro-social behavior and moral development. Before discussing the psychological research on emotional empathy and its relevance for moral philosophy and moral psychology in the next section, it is vital to introduce important conceptual distinctions that one should keep in mind in evaluating the various empirical studies.

Anyone reading the emotional empathy literature has to be struck by the fact that empathy tended to be incredibly broadly defined in the beginning of this specific research tradition. Stotland, one of the earliest researcher who understood empathy exclusively as an emotional phenomenon, defined it as “an observer’s reacting emotionally because he perceives that another is experiencing or is about to experience an emotion” (1969, 272). According to Stotland’s definition very diverse emotional responses such as feeling envy, feeling annoyed, feeling distressed, being relieved about, feeling pity, or feeling what Germans call Schadenfreude (feeling joyful about the misfortune of another) have all to be counted as empathic reactions. Since the 1980’s however, psychologists have fine tuned their understanding of empathy conceptually and distinguished between different aspects of the emotional reaction to another person; thereby implicitly acknowledging the conceptual distinctions articulated by Max Scheler (1973) almost a century earlier. In this context, it is particularly useful to distinguish between the following reactive emotions that are differentiated in respect to whether or not such reactions are self or other oriented and whether they presuppose awareness of the distinction between self and others. (See also the survey in the Introduction to Eisenberg/Strayer 1987 and Batson 2009)

Emotional contagion: Emotional contagion occurs when people start feeling similar emotions caused merely by the association with other people. You start feeling joyful, because other people around you are joyful or you start feeling panicky because you are in a crowd of people feeling panic. Emotional contagion however does not require that one is aware of the fact that one experiences the emotions because other people experience them, rather one experiences them primarily as one’s own emotion (Scheler 1973, 22). A newborn infant’s reactive cry to the distress cry of another, which Hoffman takes as a “rudimentary precursor of empathic distress” (Hoffman 2000, 65), can probably be understood as a phenomenon of emotional contagion, since the infant is not able to properly distinguish between self and other.

Affective and proper Empathy: More narrowly and properly understood, empathy in the affective sense is the vicarious sharing of an affect. Authors however differ in how strictly they interpret the phrase of vicariously sharing an affect. For some, it requires that the empathizers and the persons they empathize with need to be in very similar affective states (Coplan 2011; de Vignemont and Singer 2006; Jacob 2011). For Hoffman, on the other hand, it is an emotional response requiring only “the involvement of psychological processes that make a person have feelings that are more congruent with another’s situation than with his own situation” (Hoffman 2000, 30). According to this definition, empathy does not necessarily require that the subject and target feel similar emotions (even though this is most often the case). Rather the definition also includes cases of feeling sad when seeing a child who plays joyfully but who does not know that it has been diagnosed with a serious illness (assuming that this is how the other person himself or herself would feel if he or she would fully understand his or her situation). In contrast to mere emotional contagion, genuine empathy presupposes the ability to differentiate between oneself and the other. It requires that one is minimally aware of the fact that one is having an emotional experience due to the perception of the other’s emotion, or more generally due to attending to his situation. In seeing a sad face of another and feeling sad oneself, such feeling of sadness should count as genuinely empathic only if one recognizes that in feeling sad one’s attention is still focused on the other and that it is not an appropriate reaction to aspects of one’s own life. Moreover, empathy outside the realm of a direct perceptual encounter involves some appreciation of the other person’s emotion as an appropriate response to his or her situation. To be happy or unhappy because one’s child is happy or sad should not count necessarily as an empathic emotion. It cannot count as a vicarious emotional response if it is due to the perception of the outside world from the perspective of the observer and her desire that her children should be happy. My happiness about my child being happy would therefore not be an emotional state that is more congruent to his situation. Rather, it is an emotional response appropriate to my own perspective on the world. In order for my happiness or unhappiness to be genuinely empathic it has to be happiness or unhappiness about what makes the other person happy. Accordingly, if I share another person’s emotion vicariously I do not merely have to be in an affective state with a similar phenomenal quality. Rather my affective state has to be directed toward the same intentional object. (See Sober and Wilson 1998, 231–237 and Maibom 2007. For a critical discussion of how and whether such vicarious sharing is possible see also Deonna 2007 and Matravers 2018). It should be noted, however, that some authors conceive of proper empathy more broadly as not merely being concerned with the vicarious reenactment of affective states but more comprehensively as including non-affective states such as beliefs and desires. This is especially true if they are influenced by the discussion of of empathy as an epistemic means such as Goldman (2011) and Stueber (2006). However, already Adam Smith (1853) constitutes a good example for such broad understanding of proper empathy. Finally, others suggest that it is best to distinguish between affective sharing and perspective taking (Decety and Cowell 2015).

Sympathy: In contrast to affective empathy, sympathy—or what some authors also refer to as empathic concern—is not an emotion that is congruent with the other’s emotion or situation such as feeling the sadness of the other person’s grieving for the death of his father. Rather, sympathy is seen as an emotion sui generis that has the other’s negative emotion or situation as its object from the perspective of somebody who cares for the other person’s well being (Darwall 1998). In this sense, sympathy consists of “feeling sorrow or concern for the distressed or needy other,” a feeling for the other out of a “heightened awareness of the suffering of another person as something that needs to be alleviated.” (Eisenberg 2000a, 678; Wispe 1986, 318; and Wispe 1991).

Whereas it is quite plausible to assume that empathy—that is, empathy with negative emotions of another or what Hoffman (2000) calls “veridical empathic distress”—under certain conditions (and when certain developmental markers are achieved) can give rise to sympathy, it should be stressed that the relation between affective empathy and sympathy is a contingent one; the understanding of which requires further empirical research. First, sympathy does not necessarily require feeling any kind of congruent emotions on part of the observer, a detached recognition or representation that the other is in need or suffers might be sufficient. (See Scheler 1973 and Nichols 2004). Second, empathy or empathic distress might not at all lead to sympathy. People in the helping professions, who are so accustomed to the misery of others, suffer at times from compassion fatigue. It is also possible to experience empathic overarousal because one is emotionally so overwhelmed by one’s empathic feelings that one is unable to be concerned with the suffering of the other (Hoffman 2000, chap. 8). In the later case, one’s empathic feeling are transformed or give rise to mere personal distress, a reactive emotional phenomenon that needs to be distinguished from emotional contagion, empathy, and sympathy.

Personal Distress: Personal distress in the context of empathy research is understood as a reactive emotion in response to the perception/recognition of another’s negative emotion or situation. Yet, while personal distress is other-caused like sympathy, it is, in contrast to sympathy, primarily self-oriented . In this case, another person’s distress does not make me feel bad for him or her, it just makes me feel bad, or “alarmed, grieved, upset, worried, disturbed, perturbed, distressed,and troubled;” to use the list of adjectives that according to Batson’s research indicates personal distress (Batson et al. 1987 and Batson 1991). And, in contrast to empathic emotions as defined above, my personal distress is not any more congruent with the emotion or situation of another. Rather it wholly defines my own outlook onto the world.

While it is conceptually necessary to differentiate between these various emotional responses, it has to be admitted that it is empirically not very easy to discriminate between them, since they tend to occur together. Think or imagine yourself attending the funeral of the child of a friend or good acquaintance. This is probably one reason why early researchers tended not to distinguish between the above aspects in their study of empathy related phenomena. Yet since the above distinctions refer to very different psychological mechanisms, it is absolutely central to distinguish between them when empirically assessing the impact and contribution of empathy to an agent’s pro-social motivation and behavior. Given the ambiguity of the empathy concept within psychology—particularly in the earlier literature—in evaluating and comparing different empirical empathy studies, it is always crucial to keep in mind how empathy has been defined and measured within the context of these studies. For a more extensive discussion of the methods used by psychologists to measure empathy see the

Supplementary document on Measuring Empathy .

5. Empathy, Moral Philosophy, and Moral Psychology

Moral philosophers have always been concerned with moral psychology and with articulating an agent’s motivational structure in order to explicate the importance of morality for a human life. After all, moral judgments supposedly make demands on an agent’s will and are supposed to provide us with reasons and motivations for acting in a certain manner. Yet moral judgments, at least in the manner in which we conceive of them in modern times, are also regarded to be based on normative standards that, in contrast to mere conventional norms, have universal scope and are valid independent of the features of specific social practices that agents are embedded in. One only needs to think of statements such as “cruelty to innocent children or slavery is morally wrong,” which we view as applying also to social practices where the attitude of its population seem to condone such actions. Moral judgements thus seem to address us from the perspective of the moral stance where we leave behind the perspective of self-love and do not conceive of each other either as friends or foes (see Hume 1987, 75) or as belonging to the in–group or out–group, but where we view each other all to be equal part of a moral community. Finally, and relatedly, in order to view morality as something that is possible for human beings we also seem to require that our motivations based on or associated with moral reasons have a self-less character. Given to charity for merely selfish reasons, for example, seems to clearly diminish its moral worth and implicitly deny the universal character of a moral demand. Philosophically explicating the importance of morality for human life then has to do the following: It has to explain how it is that we humans as a matter of fact do care about morality thusly conceived, it has to address the philosophically even more pertinent question of why it is that we should care about morality or why it is that we should regard judgments issued from the perspective of the moral stance to have normative authority over us; and it has to allow us to understand how it is that we can act self-lessly in a manner that correspond to the demands made on us from the moral stance. Answering all of these questions however necessitates at one point to explain how our moral interests are related to our psychological constitution as human beings and how moral demands can be understood as being appropriately addressed to agents who are psychologically structured in that manner.

Prima facie, the difficulty of this enterprise consists in squaring a realistic account of human psychology with the universal scope and intersubjective validity of moral judgments, since human motivation and psychological mechanisms seem to be always situational, local, and of rather limited scope. Moreover, as evolutionary psychologists tell us in–group bias seems to be a universal trait of human psychology. One of the most promising attempts to solve this problem is certainly due to the tradition of eighteenth century moral philosophy associated with the names of David Hume and Adam Smith who tried to address all of the above philosophical desiderata by pointing to the central role that our empathic and sympathetic capacities have for constituting us as social and moral agents and for providing us with the psychological capacities to make and to respond to moral judgments. While philosophers in the Kantian tradition, who favor reason over sentiments, have generally been skeptical about this proposal, more recently the claim that empathy is central for morality and a flourishing human life has again been the topic of an intense and controversial debate. On the one hand, empathy has been hailed by researchers from a wide range of disciplines and also by some public figures, President Obama most prominently among them. Slote (2010) champions empathy as the sole foundation of moral judgment, de Waal (2006) conceives of it as the unique evolutionary building block of morality, Rifkin (2009) regards it even as a force whose cultivation has unique revolutionary powers to transform a world in crisis, and Baron-Cohen (2011, 194) views it as a “universal solvent” in that “any problem immersed in empathy becomes soluble.” On the other hand, such empathy enthusiasm has encountered penetrating criticism by Prinz (2011 a,b) and Bloom (2016), who emphasize its dark side, that is, its tendency to fall prey to so–called “here and now” biases. The following subsections will address these issues by surveying the relevant empirical research on the question whether empathy motivates us in a self-less manner, the question of whether empathy is inherently biased and partial to the in-group, and it will discuss how we might think of the normative character of moral judgments in light of our empathic capacities.(For a survey of other relevant issues from social psychology, specifically social neuroscience, consult also Decety and Lamm 2006; Decety and Ickes 2009, and Decety 20012. For a discussion of the importance empathy for medical practice see Halpern 2001)

In a series of ingeniously designed experiments, Batson has accumulated evidence for what he calls the empathy-altruism thesis. In arguing for this thesis, Batson conceives of empathy as empathic concern or what others would call sympathy. More specifically, he characterized it in terms of feelings of being sympathetic, moved by, being compassionate, tender, warm and soft-hearted towards the other’s plight (Batson et al. 1987, 26) The task of his experiments consists in showing that empathy/sympathy does indeed lead to genuinely altruistic motivation, where the welfare of the other is the ultimate goal of my helping behavior, rather than to helping behavior because of predominantly egoistic motivations. According to the egoistic interpretation of empathy–related phenomena, empathizing with another person in need is associated with a negative feeling or can lead to a heightened awareness of the negative consequences of not helping; such as feelings of guilt, shame, or social sanctions. Alternatively, it can lead to an enhanced recognition of the positive consequences of helping behavior such as social rewards or good feelings. Empathy according to this interpretation induces us to help through mediation of purely egoistic motivations. We help others only because we recognize helping behavior as a means to egoistic ends. It allows us to reduce our negative feelings (aversive arousal reduction hypothesis), to avoid “punishment,” or to gain specific internal or external “rewards” (empathy-specific punishment and empathy-specific reward hypotheses).

Notice however that in arguing for the empathy-altruism thesis, Batson is not claiming that empathy always induces helping behavior. Rather, he argues against the predominance of an egoistic interpretation of an agent’s motivational structure. He argues for the existence of genuinely altruistic motivations and more specifically for the claim that empathy causes such genuinely altruistic motivation. These genuinely altruistic motives (together with other egoistic motives) are taken into account by the individual agent in deliberating about whether or not to help. Even for Batson, the question of whether the agent will act on his or her altruistic motivations depends ultimately on how strong they are and what costs the agent would incur in helping another person.

The basic set up of Batson’s experiments consists in the manipulation of the situation of the experimental subjects (dependent on the egoistic alternative to be argued against) and the manipulation of empathy/sympathy felt for an observed target in need. The decisive evidence for the empathy/sympathy-altruism thesis is always the recorded behavior of the subject, who is in a high empathy condition and in a situation where his helping behavior can not plausibly be seen as a means for the satisfaction of a personal goal. Since here is not the place to extensively describe the details of Batson’s experiments, a brief description of the experimental set up—focusing on Batson’s argument against the aversive arousal interpretation of empathy—and a brief evaluation of the success of his general argumentative strategy has to suffice (for more details see Batson 1991 and 2011). In all of his experiments, Batson assumes—based on Stotland (1969) and others—that empathy/sympathy can be manipulated either by manipulating the perceived similarity between subjects and targets or by manipulating the perspective taking attitude of the subjects. Empathy according to these assumptions can be increased by enhancing the perceived similarity between subject and target or by asking the subject to imagine how the observed person would feel in his or her situation rather than asking the subject to attend carefully to the information provided. [Note also that instructing the subject to imagine how they themselves would feel in the other’s situation, rather than instructing them to imagine how the other feels, is associated with an increase in personal distress and not only sympathetic feelings. (Batson et al. 1997b and Lamm, Batson, and Decety 2007).]

In trying to argue against the aversive arousal reduction interpretation, Batson also manipulates the ease with which a subject can avoid helping another person (in this case taking his place when they see him getting electric shocks). He reasons that if empathy leads to genuinely altruistic motivations, subjects in the high empathy/easy escape condition should still be willing to help. If they were only helping in order to reduce their own negative feelings, they would be expected to leave in this situation, since leaving is the less costly means for reaching an egoistic goal. As Batson was happy to report, the results confirmed his empathy/sympathy-altruism hypothesis, not only in the above experiments but also in experiments testing other alternative interpretations of empathy such as the empathy- specific punishment and the empathy-specific award hypotheses.

Researchers generally agree in finding Batson’s experimental research program and the accumulated evidence for the empathy-altruism thesis to be impressive. Yet they disagree about how persuasive one should ultimately regard his position. In particular it has been pointed out that his experiments have limited value, since they target only very specific egoistic accounts of why empathy might lead to helping behavior. Batson is not able to dismiss conclusively every alternative egoistic interpretation. In addition, it has been claimed that egoism has the resources to account for the result of his experiments. For example, one might challenge the validity of Batson’s interpretation by speculating whether empathy/sympathy leads to a heightened awareness of the fact that one will be troubled by bad memories of seeing another person in need, if one does nothing to help him or her. In this case even an egoistically motivated person would help in the high empathy/easy escape condition. (For this reply and various other egoistic interpretations of Batson’s experiments see Sober and Wilson 1998, 264–271).

Cialdini and his collaborators have suggested an even more elaborate non-altruistic interpretation of helping behavior in high empathy/easy escape conditions. According to their suggestions, conditions of high empathy are also conditions of increased “interpersonal unity, wherein the conception of self and other are not distinct but are merged to some degree” (Cialdini et al. 1997, 490). It is this increased feeling of oneness rather than empathy that is causally responsible for motivating helping behavior (See however Batson et al. 1997a, Neuberg et al. 1997, and Batson 1997 and 2011 for a plausible reply and May 2018, 144–153 for a probing discussion of the relation between empathic concern and oneness). One therefore has to be cautious in claiming that Batson has conclusively proven that the empathy/sympathy-altruism hypothesis is true, if that means one has logically excluded every egoistic alternative in accounting for helping behavior. But it has to be acknowledged that Batson has radically changed the argumentative dialectic of the egoism-altruism debate by forcing the egoistic account of human agency to come up with ever more elaborate alternative interpretations in order to account for helping behavior within its framework. Egoism was supposed to provide a rather unified and relatively simple account of the motivational structure of human agency. In challenging the predominance and simplicity of this framework in an empirically acute fashion, Batson has at least established altruism—claiming that besides egoistic motivations we are also motivated by genuinely altruistic reasons—as an empirically plausible hypothesis. He has shown it to be a hypothesis one is almost persuaded to believe that it is true, as he himself recently has characterized his own epistemic attitude (Batson 1997, 522.) More positively expressed, Batson’s research has at least demonstrated that empathy/sympathy is a causal factor in bringing about helping behavior. Regardless of the question of the exact nature of the underlying motivation for helping or prosocial behavior, psychologists generally assume that in adults and children a positive, even if weak, correlation between empathy—measured in a variety of ways—and prosocial behavior has been established; and this despite the fact that the above aspects of emotional responding to another person have not always been sufficiently distinguished.(For a survey see Eisenberg and Miller 1987; Eisenberg/Fabes 1998, Spinrad and Eisenberg 2014. For a general survey of the various factors contributing to prosocial behavior see Bierhoff 2002).

Regardless of how exactly one views the strength of Batson’s position, his research alone does not validate the thesis, articulated by various traditional moral philosophers, that sympathy or empathy is the basis of morality or that it constitutes the only source for moral motivation. First, nothing in his research has shown that empathy/sympathy is empirically necessary for moral agency. Second, some of Batson’s own research casts doubt on the claim that sympathy/empathy is the foundation of morality as empathy induced altruism can lead to behavior that conflicts with our principles of justice and fairness. One, for example, tends to assign a better job or a higher priority for receiving medical treatment to persons with whom one has actually sympathized, in violation of the above moral principles (See Batson et al. 1995). For that very reason, Batson himself distinguishes between altruistic motivation concerned with the well-being of another person and moral motivation guided by principles of justice and fairness (Batson 2011). Unfortunately we do not always realize this fact when we abstractly contrast moral motivation broadly with egoistic motivation. For that very reason, we also do not realize that we need to be more conscious in “orchestrating” the relationship between altruistic and moral motivations in order to fully utilize the motivational power of altruism for moral purposes (Batson 2014). Finally, the research discussed so far is not relevant for deciding the question of whether sophisticated mindreading abilities are required for full blown moral agency, since Batson understands empathy primarily as an emotional phenomenon. (See Nichols 2001 and Batson et al. 2003 in this respect.)

Within the psychological literature, one of the most comprehensive accounts of empathy and its relation to the moral development of a person is provided by the work of Martin Hoffman (for a summary see his 2000). Hoffman views empathy as a biologically based disposition for altruistic behavior (Hoffman 1981). He conceives of empathy as being due to various modes of arousal allowing us to respond empathically in light of a variety of distress cues from another person. Hoffman mentions mimicry, classical conditioning, and direct association—where one empathizes because the other’s situation reminds one of one’s own painful experience—as “fast acting and automatic” mechanisms producing an empathic response. As more cognitively demanding modes, Hoffman lists mediated association—where the cues for an empathic response are provided in a linguistic medium—and role taking.

Hoffman distinguishes between six (or more) developmental stages of empathic responses ranging from the reactive newborn cry, egocentric empathic distress, quasi-ego-centric empathic distress, to veridical empathy, empathy for another beyond the immediate situation, and empathy for whole groups of people. Accordingly, empathic responses constitute a developmental continuum that ranges from emotional contagion (as in the case of a reactive newborn cry) to various forms of proper empathy reached at the fourth stage. At the developmentally later stages, the child is able to emotionally respond to the distress of another in a more sophisticated manner due to an increase of cognitive capacities, particularly due to the increased cognitive ability to distinguish between self and other and by becoming aware of the fact that others have mental states that are independent from its own. Only at the fourth stage of empathic development (after the middle of the second year) do children acquire such abilities. They do no longer try to comfort themselves, when emotionally responding to another child’s distress—like seeking comfort from their own mother—, or use helping strategies that are more appropriate to comfort themselves than the other person—like using their own teddy-bear in trying to comfort the other child. Only at the fourth stage does empathy become also transformed or associated with sympathy leading to appropriate prosocial behavior. Hoffman’s developmental view is further supported by Preston and DeWaal’s account of empathy as a phenomenon to be observed across species at various levels of complexities related to different degrees of cognitive development. (Preston and DeWaal 2002a,b. For a discussion of the philosophical relevance of DeWaal’s view see also DeWaal 2006).

Significantly, Hoffman combines his developmental explication of empathy with a sophisticated analysis of its importance for moral agency. He is thereby acutely aware of the limitations in our natural capacity to empathize or sympathize with others, particularly what he refers to as “here and now” biases, that is, the fact that we tend to empathize more with persons that are in some sense perceived to be closer to us. (For a neuro-scientific investigation of how racial bias modulates empathic responses see Xuo, Zuo, Wang and Han 2009). Like Batson, Hoffman does not regard the moral realm as being exclusively circumscribed by our ability to empathize with other people. Besides empathic abilities, moral agency requires also knowledge of abstract moral principles, such as the principles of caring and justice. Hoffman seems to conceive of those principles as being derived from cognitive sources that are independent from our empathic abilities. Yet Hoffmann is rather optimistic about the natural compatibility of empathic motivation and our commitment to moral principles. He regards stable and effective moral agency as requiring empathy so that moral principles can have a motivational basis in an agent’s psychology. Within this context, he has lately emphasized a final stage of empathy development or what he calls “witnessing”, an empathic response to the suffering of others that is so intense that we “become fully committed to help”(Hoffman 2014, 82). As he explains—in light of examples from the history of abolitionism, the civil rights movement, serfdom reform in Russia, and various cases before the Supreme Court— it is particularly such witnessing that has contributed towards bending the arc of the moral universe towards justice. Accordingly, and despite our natural limitations in empathizing with others, Hoffman still regards empathy as the “bedrock of morality” and “the glue of society”(Hoffman 2014, 96. Besides Hoffman 2011 and 2014, see also Deigh 2011 for a measured evaluation of empathy in the legal context ).

More recently, such ultimately positive evaluation of empathy’s contributing role in constituting us as moral agents, as agents who address each other from the moral stance, has encountered penetrating criticism, particularly by Prinz (2011a,b) and Bloom (2016). Both emphasize the dark side of empathy, that is, the aforementioned “here and now” biases. More specifically Prinz mentions explicitly the cuteness, salience, and proximity effects—the fact that we tend to empathize more easily with attractive persons, with persons that are in close proximity and only if their suffering is particularly noteworthy— similarity biases and the fact that we tend to be rather selective in choosing whom to empathize with. Empathy is also very easily modulated by a variety of top-down factors that influence our perception of the social world and that let us register social divisions that seem to be prima facie incompatible with the more impartial stance demanded by the moral perspective. Research has documented these biases in a more fine-grained manner and shown that subjects generally “reported experiencing more empathy for the in–group then the out–group targets and more counter–empathy for the out–group than in–group targets”(Cikara et. al. 2014, 120), counter–empathy here being understood as the feeling of pleasure at the misfortune of another (Schadenfreude) or the feeling displeasure at something fortunate happening to another (Glückschmerz). This is particularly true if the other group is viewed to be in competition with one’s own group. Empathy can also be further reduced through various dehumanizing and objectifying strategies, strategies that have certainly employed in the context of the genocides of the twentieth century and the system of racial slavery in the United States (See Fuchs 2019, Kteily and Bruneau 2017). Heightened empathy for perceived wrongs done to members of the in–group can also lead to violent and immoral behavior (Bloom 2016, chap. 5). In addition, empathy tends to focus on the one (particularly if he or she is identifiable) rather than the many, what Bloom refers to as its spotlight feature. Empathy can mislead us particularly in contexts where we need to take into account statistically relevant information when addressing a moral or social problem, such as when thinking about the benefits of vaccination where it is more appropriate to think about the large numbers of children saved rather than empathizing with the bad effects such vaccination might have on one specific child. For all of these reasons, Prinz favors the moral emotions such as anger, guilt and shame as the foundation for morality, while Bloom prefers sympathy guided by reason as a more viable means than empathy to steer us in moral matters.

Here is not the place for a final evaluation of empathy’s contribution in regard to pro-social and moral motivation or moral and pro-social behavior, since this question is still very much the topic of an ongoing empirical investigation. Yet the following observations are certainly justified in light of the empirical evidence so far and might help to further clarify the debate. First, it seems to be pretty well established that however one defines our natural capacity for empathy, it is on its own not sufficient to keep us reliably on the path of morality (See also Decety and Cowell 2015). Whether that ultimately means that we should think of our capacity for empathy as a limited resource or whether it would be better to think of empathy as a motivated phenomenon and its limitations as being due to our reluctance to activate that capacity (Zaki 2014), is certainly another intriguing question for further empirical inquiry. One might also wonder why we should expect that the emotions such as sympathy and anger, which Bloom and Prinz point to, are less prone to bias and less affected by a universal human tendency to favor the in–group. Certainly sympathy within the context of Buddhism, to which Bloom appeals to is a highly regulated emotion, controlled through mindfulness practices or meditation and guided by an intellectual grasp about the detriments of various forms of attachment to this world. Persson and Savulescu (2018) therefore suggest that rather than giving up on empathy completely one should reform empathy by regulating it through one’s reflective capacities in light of our knowledge of its natural shortcomings or focus one’s empathy (cognitive and affective) particularly on another person’s concerns for his or her well-being as such empathy includes sympathy for the other (Simmons 2014). Such suggestions are also very much in line with proposals by David Hume and Adam Smith, who suggested already in the eighteenth century that we need to regulate empathy with the help of certain corrective mechanisms such as “some steady and general points of view” or the perspective of the“impartial spectator” in order to compensate for empathy’s limited scope. (For a good analysis of the philosophical discussion about empathy/sympathy in the eighteenth century see Frazer 2010).

Most importantly, in order to evaluate the empirical discussion about empathy’s role for morality, one needs to be very sensitive to how researchers define and measure empathy in arguing for and against empathy’s relation to moral motivation or moral judgment. Prinz and Bloom are quite explicit in defining empathy merely as an affective phenomenon, as our ability to feel what the other person feels. Evidence suggests indeed that merely sharing another person’s emotion empathically does not increase our concern or motivation for moral or pro-social action. Interestingly, however, perspective–taking and empathic concern/sympathy, which have always been seen as an integral part of empathy-related phenomena, are a slightly different matter. They do seem to be positively related to cooperation and charitable giving (Jordon et. al. 2016), to reducing prejudices against particular groups (Galinski and Morowitz 2011), and to an increase in one’s sensitivity to injustices done to others (Decety and Yoder 2015). Yet even here further research is needed as the effects of such perspective–taking could be modulated by the power differential between groups. It has, for example, been shown that in active intergroup conflicts, positive intergroup interaction can increase empathy for the other group. Yet within such contexts, taking the perspective of a person from the other group while interacting with them might also hinder the development of intergroup empathy if the dominant group is reminded through such perspective–taking of how they might be viewed by the non-dominant group. Even perspective taking by the non–dominant group might increase rather than decrease established negative stereotypes in thinking about the other group (Cikara et. al. 2014). It seems more effective if the non–dominant group is asked to articulate the difficulties of their lives (perspective–giving) and the dominant group is asked to translate that description into their own words (perspective–taking), even if the positive effects of such interaction is relatively short-lived (Bruneau and Saxe 2012).

So far, this entry has discussed mainly research exploring the relation between empathy and prosocial/moral behavior or motivation. Other important areas for considering empathy’s role in moral matters have to do with addressing the questions of how and whether empathy contributes to our ability to distinguish between moral and conventional norms, to the making of moral judgments, and how empathy can be appealed to in explicating the normative authority of such judgments. In considering the first question, psychologists and philosophers have generally followed Turiel in understanding moral norms as expressing concerns for “rights, justice, and the welfare of other people” (Turiel 1983, 3) and as having a very specific “signature response patterns” (Kelly et. al. 2007) associated with it. Moral norms are generally regarded to be more important than conventional norms in that their normative validity is conceived as being independent of social authority or specific social practices and agreements. Their scope is also judged to be much broader—they are thought of to be valid in other countries, for example—, and violation of moral norms is generally understood to be a more serious offense than the violation of other norms. Notice however that in distinguishing between moral and conventional norms subjects do not necessarily associate a strict universality in the Kantian sense with moral norms and view them as applicable to all rational beings. Indeed there is some evidence that 6–9 year old children, for example, view the moral/conventional distinction as being fully applicable only to behavior of individuals in the in-group and view prescription against harming members of the out-group to be more like conventional norms (Rhodes and Chalik 2013). Accordingly, the fact that empathy shows considerable in-group bias, as discussed above, does not automatically count as evidence against it playing a role in allowing humans to distinguish between moral and conventional norms within a social context.

Of central importance for assessing the role of empathy for grasping the moral/conventional distinction has been the research on the nature of psychopathy and autism. Both pathologies are seen as involving deficits in different dimensions of empathy but only psychopaths have great difficulties in living up to moral standards of their societies and only they were originally thought of as having difficulties in appropriately distinguishing between moral and conventional norms (Blair 1995 and 1996). More specifically, psychopaths show a selective deficit in affective or emotional empathy particularly in “processing fearful, sad, and possibly disgusted facial expressions”(Blair 2010, 710). In contrast to persons with autism they however do not show similar deficits in perspective taking or theory of mind capacities. In his 1995 article, Blair therefore blames the absence of what he calls the Violence Inhibition Mechanism(VIM) that allows us to respond appropriately to the observed distress cues in others for the psychopaths’ moral deficits and their inability to draw the moral/conventional distinction. In his later work, he speaks more broadly of a dysfunction of our Integrated Emotion System (IES), caused by a deficit in the amygdala to properly represent negative emotions. (Blair, Mitchel, and Blair 2005, for a recent survey regarding the very specific deficit of psychopaths in feeling and recognizing fear see also Marsh 2014). Yet one has to tread very carefully in drawing definite conclusions about the role of empathy for morality from the empirical research about psychopathy. The results of the empirical investigations are far from unified and do not point in the same direction (For a concise survey see Maibom 2017). Newer studies, for example, seem to suggest that psychopaths, as measured by the overall score of the revised psychopathy checklist (PCL–R), are able to understand the distinction between moral and conventional norms if tested under a forced choice paradigm (Aharoni et. al 2012.)Nevertheless even that study seems to allow for the possibility that emotional deficits are responsible for the psychopath’s shortcomings in accurately drawing the distinction since they are somewhat linked to the affective and antisocial facets of the PCL–R. Given the inconsistent results of the various studies, other researchers prefer to view a psychopath’s immorality not as a specific deficit in empathy, but understand it to be caused by their general inability to feel strong emotions, by their general coldheartedness, or even by shortcomings in their rational and prudential capacities. From that perspective, a psychopath might understand in an abstract manner that certain things are morally wrong to do, but he just does not care for morality, the welfare of another person, or even for himself. (For further discussion see Maibom 2005 and 2009, Nichols 2004, and Prinz 2011a,b). Similar considerations apply also to research regarding subjects with autism. Kennett (2002)has argued that evidence from autistic individuals, whose imaginative role-play and thus empathic capacities are diminished, does not support the claim that empathy is necessary for moral agency. Yet in her arguments she only considers the fact that persons with autism have difficulties with putting themselves in another person’s shoes but does not consider that they seem to have some ability to pick up on the emotional states of other people as revealed by their facial expressions. Moreover, while autistic subjects in general can distinguish between moral and conventional norms they do seem to lack a certain flexibility in evaluating the seriousness of the violation of a moral norm when they reflect on moral dilemmas or when they encounter an accidental or unintentional violation of such norms. (See McGeer 2008, Zalla et. al 2011, but see also Kennett 2011 and Leslie et. al. 2006 in response).

Philosophers have however not been merely be interested in appealing to empathy for explicating the psychological basis for our thinking that certain norms have moral status. Within the general framework of moral sentimentalism, which sees morality generally linked to our emotional responsiveness to the actions of others and ourselves, they have also appealed to empathy in explicating more generally the nature of moral judgments (see also Kauppinen 2014 and 2017a). David Hume, for example, has suggested that moral judgments are based on peculiar sentiments of moral approbations and disapprobation, which are causally mediated by our ability to empathize— or what he called sympathy— with the pain and pleasures of others (See also Sayre-Mcord 1994 and 2014). More specifically, sentiments of moral approbations arise in response to our ability to think about and enliven the pleasure and pain that others feel with the help of our empathic/sympathetic capacities when we consider the benefits (the pleasure and pain) which a person’s character traits and actions provide to himself and others. Yet Hume was already quite aware of some of the above mentioned limitations and biases of our natural willingness and capacity to empathize with others. Accordingly, he insisted that sentiments of approbations can only be conceived of as moral approbation if empathy/sympathy is regulated or corrected by what he refers to as “steady and general points of view” (Hume 1739–40 [1978], 581/2) so that our capacity for sympathy enables us to “touch a string, to which all mankind have an accord and symphony” (Hume 1748 [1983], 75). There are certainly a number of issues that can be raised in response to Hume’s proposal. Suffice it here to point out that it is difficult to fully understand how Hume is ultimately able distinguish between judgments about something being bad and something being morally wrong. Certainly natural disasters also cause us to sympathize/empathize with the pain it causes others, yet such sympathy is not mediating any judgments about the moral impermissibility of natural disasters. Hume himself might have thought to have solved this problem by thinking that sentiments of moral approbation have a peculiar or distinct character (see in this respect particularly Debes 2012). Yet pointing to the peculiarity of such sentiments seems to be rather unsatisfying for answering this challenge.

Michael Slote, one of the main contemporary proponents of the claim that empathy plays a constitutive role for moral judgments, does not follow Hume in thinking that empathy plays a moral role in allowing us to pick up on a subject’s pleasure and pain. Rather Slote, who also has been influenced by a feminist ethics of care (Slote 2007, 2010), suggests that empathy is central for moral approval in that we as spectators empathically pick up on whether or not an agent acted out of empathic concern for another subject. Moral approval of an action consists then in the subsequent reflective feeling of warmth when empathizing with an agent’s empathic concern, while moral disapproval is equivalent with a reflective feeling of chill due to our recognition that the agent acted without any empathic concern. Actions are then judged to be morally right or wrong in terms of whether they can be conceived of the actions of an agent we would morally approve of in that they are actions done out of empathic concern. Notice also that while Slote does regard empathy in the above sense to be constitutive of moral approval only if it is fully or well–developed, he does not follow Hume in thinking that empathy needs to be regulated in order to correct for some of its natural partiality. Indeed Slote thinks that this is a virtue of his account since he regards such partiality reflected in our moral intuitions. For example, he thinks that we have a greater moral obligation to help the child in front of us or members of our family rather than people who are more removed from us. Slote certainly deserves credit for reviving the debate about the role of empathy for morality in contemporary metaethics. Yet his conception of the relation between empathy and morality has also encountered some skepticism. First of all, it is questionable that only motivations of empathic concern, rather than the thought that one is doing the right thing, constitute proper moral motivations. Second, in light of the above research on empathy’s bias and natural shortcomings, it is rather questionable to maintain that all aspects of empathy’s partiality are sanctioned by our our moral intuitions. It is therefore hard to see how empathy’s moral role can be justified without appeal to some form of corrective mechanism. Third, phenomenologically speaking, moral disapproval is not necessarily based on a “chilly” feeling. At times we are rather upset and angry in encountering violations of moral norms. Finally, Slote’s proposed empathic mechanism underlying moral approval seems to lack a certain psychological plausibility. For Slote, we approve of an action because we recreate the empathic concern that the agent feels towards his or her subjects and that causes us to feel warmly towards the agent. Yet if a positive moral judgment of an actions is tied to providing us with the motivation or with a reason for doing a specific action, it is hard to see how moral approval, consisting in us feeling warmly towards the agent, should help us accomplish this. If Slote is right, it would rather provide us with a reason for merely praising or being nice towards the agent (See D’Arms 2011, Kauppinen 2014 and 2017a, Prinz 2001a,b, and Stueber 2011c).

There is one additional element to consider when debating empathy’s contribution to morality. Philosophers are not merely interested in answering factual and causal questions of why we care about morality, what causal role empathy plays in this respect, or how empathy causally contributes in allowing us to distinguish between moral and conventional norms and judging what is morally right or wrong. Rather they are also interested in genuinely normative questions in attempting to answer the question of why we should care about morality and why we should regard moral judgments as making normative demands on us. In morally blaming other persons we do assume that we evaluate their behavior according to standards that they as persons are in some sense already committed to. We assume that these standards are their own standards rather than standards that we impose from an external perspective on them. Unfortunately, even if one would agree with either David Hume or Michael’s Slote’s account of the causal role of empathy outlined above, it is doubtful that their account would help us to answer the genuinely normative question appropriately. Why exactly should I take a particular emotional reaction of another person towards me and my action, even if it is a feeling of warmth caused by empathy, as something that is normatively relevant for me. Certainly we all like to be liked and try to fit in with our peer group, but then moral judgments would be nothing more than a glorified form of peer pressure. Hume might respond that we should take them seriously because they are responses from the general point of view, but that in itself seems to be begging the question of why such perspective is articulating the appropriate normative standard for judging our behavior and character. This is also exactly the reason, why philosophers with Kantian inclinations have been in general skeptical about moral sentimentalism and positions that think of empathy as a foundation of morality (for a nice explication of Kant’s critical view of sympathy see Deimling 2017). Contemporary “Kantians” do at times, however, admit that empathy and perspective taking is epistemically relevant for moral deliberations, even if it is not solely constitutive for moral agency (Deigh 1996 and 2018; Darwall 2006, Shermann 1998, For a review see also Oxley 2011). Interestingly, philosophers sympathetic to moral sentimentalism have particularly turned to Adam Smith for inspiration in developing empathy based accounts of morality and in responding to the above normativity problem. In contrast to Hume, Smith conceives of empathy/sympathy not merely as the enlivening of a perceived emotion or feeeling but as imaginative perspective–taking. In taking up another person’s perspective we put ourselves in his situation and imagine how he would respond to the situation, how he would think and feel about it. If in bringing another person’s point of view “home to ourselves” in this manner, we recognize that we ourselves might have felt or acted like the other person, then we approve of the other person’s sentiment or action, otherwise we disapprove. Moreover, such approval constitutes moral approval if we have empathized with the other from the perspective of the impartial spectator, a perspective that Smith, like Hume, appeals to in order to correct for empathy’s natural shortcomings. More importantly, some authors think that within the Smithian framework we also find some answers to the normativity problem. They think that the impartial spectator perspective can be recast as an implicit commitment of our ordinary practice of making sense of each other as rational and emotional creatures with the help of empathic perspective taking (Stueber 2017) or argue that Smithian perspective–taking involves quasi-Kantian commitments to the dignity of a person, including his or her affective dimension. (Debes 2017, but see also Fricke 2005, Kauppinen 2017b, and Roughley 2018).

  • Abel, T., 1948. “The Operation Called Verstehen ,” The American Journal of Sociology , 54: 211–18; reprinted in Dallmayr, Fred and Thomas McCarthy (eds.), Understanding and Social Inquiry , Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1977.
  • Aharoni,E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., and Kiehl, K.A., 2012. “Can Psychopathic Offenders Discern Moral Wrong? A New Look at the Moral/Conventional Distinction,” Journal of Abnormal Psychology , 121: 484–497.
  • Allen, C., 2010. “Miror, Mirror in the Brain, what’s the Monkey Stand to Gain?” Noûs , 44: 372–391.
  • Baron-Cohen, S., 2003. The Essential Difference: The Truth about the Male and Female Brain , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 2011. The Science of Evil: On Empathy and the Origins of Cruelty , New York: Basic Books.
  • Baron-Cohen, S. and S. Wheelwright, 2004: “The Empathy Quotient: An Investigation of Adults with Asperger Syndrome or High Functioning Autism, and Normal Sex Differences,” Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders , 34: 163–175.
  • Batson, C.D., 1991. The Altruism Question: Toward a Social Psychological Answer , Hillsdale, NJ.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
  • –––, 1997. “Self-Other Merging and the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis: Reply to Neuberg et al.,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 73: 517–522.
  • –––, 2009. “ These Things Called Empathy: Eight Related But Distinct Phenomona,” The Social Neuroscience of Empathy , J. Decety and W. Ickes (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 3–15.
  • –––, 2011. Altruism in Humans , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2014. “Empathy–Induced Altruism and Morality: No Necessary Connection,” in Empathy and Morality , H. Maibom (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 41–58.
  • Batson, C.D., J. Fultz, and P. Schoenrade, 1987. “Distress and Empathy: Two Qualitatively Distinct Vicarious Emotions with Different Motivational Consequences,” Journal of Personality 55: 19–39.
  • Batson, C.D., R.R. Klein, L. Highberger, and L.L. Shaw, 1995. “Immorality From Empathy-Induced Altruism: When Compassion and Justice Conflict,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 68: 1042–1054.
  • Batson, C.D., K. Sager, E. Garst, M. Kang, K. Rubchinsky, and K. Dawson, 1997a. “Is Empathy Induced Helping Due to Self-Other Merging?,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73: 495–509.
  • Batson, C.D., S. Early, and G.Salvarini, 1997b. “Perspective Taking: Imagining how Another Feels versus Imagining how You Would Feel,” Personality and Social Personality Bulletin , 23: 751–758.
  • Batson, C.D., D. Lishner, A.Carpenter, L. Dulin, S. Harjusola-Wevv, E. L. Stocks, S. Gale, O. Hassan, and B. Sampat, 2003. “‘…As you Would Have Them Do Unto You’: Does Imagining Yourself in the Other’s Place Stimulate Moral Action?,” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin , 29: 1190–1201.
  • Bierhoff, H.-W., 2002. Prosocial Behavior , East Sussex: Psychology Press.
  • Blair, R., 1996. “Brief Report: Morality in the Autistic Child,” Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 26: 571–579.
  • Blair, R., D. Mitchell, and D. Blair, 2005. The Psychopath , Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Bloom, P., 2016. Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion , New York: Ecco.
  • Borg, E., 2007. “If Mirror Neurons Are the Answer, What was the Question?” Journal of Consciousness Studies , 14: 5–19.
  • Breithaupt, F., 2009. Kulturen der Empathie , Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
  • Bruneau, E. and R. Saxe. 2012. “The Power of Being Heard: The Benefits of ‘;Perspective-Giving’; in the Context of Intergroup Conflict,” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 48: 855–866.
  • Choplan, B., M. McCain, J. Carbonell, and R. Hagen, 1985. “Empathy: Review of Available Measures,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 48: 635–653.
  • Churchland, P., 1970. “The Logical Character of Action-Explanations,” The Philosophical Review , 79, 214–236.
  • Cialdini, R.B., S.L. Brown, B.P. Lewis, C. Luce, and S.L. Neuberg, 1997. “Reinterpreting the Empathy-Altruism Relationship: When One Into One Equals Oneness,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 73: 481–494.
  • Cikara, M., E. Bruneau, J.J. Van Bavel, and R. Saxe. 2014. “Their Pain Gives Us Pleasure: How Intergroup Dynamics Shape Empathic Failures and Counter–Empathic Responses,” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 55: 110–115.
  • Collingwood, R.G., 1946. The Idea of History , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Coplan, A., 2011. “Understanding Empathy: Its Features and Effects,” in Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3–18.
  • Coplan, A. and P. Goldie (eds.), 2011. Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Cronbach, L., 1955. “Processes Affecting Scores on ‘Understanding of Others’ and ‘Assumed Similarity’,” Psychological Bulletin , 52: 177–193.
  • Csibra, F., 2007. “Action Mirroring and Action Interpretation: An Alternative Account,” in Sensorimotor Foundations of Higher Cognition (Attention and Performance XII) , ed. P. Haggard, Y. Rosetti and M. Kawato, 435–459. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Currie, G., and I. Ravenscroft, 2002. Recreative Minds , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Curtis, R. and G. Koch, 2009. Einfühlung: Zur Geschichte und Gegenwart eines ästhetischen Konzepts , München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
  • Danto, Arthur, 1965. Analytical Philosophy of History , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • D’Arms, J., 2011. “Empathy, Approval, and Disapproval in Moral Sentimentalism,” Sourthern Journal of Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), 49: 134–141.
  • Darwall, S., 1998. “Empathy, Sympathy, and Care,” Philosophical Studies , 89: 261–282.
  • –––, 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Davies M., and T. Stone (eds.), 1995. Folk Psychology , Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • Davis, M., 1980. “A Multidimensional Approach to Individual Differences in Empathy”. JSAS Catalog of Selected Documents in Psychology , 10: 85.
  • –––, 1983. “Measuring Individual Differences in Empathy: Evidence for a Multidimensional Approach,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 44: 113–126.
  • –––, 1994. Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach , Boulder: Westview Press.
  • Davis, M. and L. Kraus, 1997. “Personality and Empathic Accuracy,” in Empathic Accuracy , W. Ickes (ed.), New York/London: Guilford Press, 144–168.
  • Debes, R., 2010. “Which Empathy? Limitations in the Mirrored ”Understanding“ of Emotions,” Synthese , 175: 219–239.
  • –––, 2012. “Recasting Scottish Sentimentalism: The Pecularity of Moral Approval,” Journal of Scottish Philosophy , 10(1): 91–115.
  • –––, 2017. “The Authority of Empathy (Or How to Ground Sentimentalism),” in Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives , R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 171–191.
  • Decety, J. 2010, “To What Extent is the Experience of Empathy Mediated by Shared Neural Circuits?,” Emotion Review , 2(3): 204–207.
  • –––, 2012. Empathy: From Bench to Bedside , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Decety, J. and J.M. Cowell, 2015. “Empathy, Justice, and Moral Behavior,” AJOB Neuroscience , 6: 3–14.
  • Decety, J. and C. Lamm, 2006. “Human Empathy through the Lens of Social Neuroscience,” The Scientific World Journal , 6: 1146–1163.
  • Decety, J. and W. Ickes, 2009. The Social Neuroscience of Empathy , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Decety, J. and K.J. Joder, 2016. “Empathy and Motivation for Justice: Cognitive Empathy and Concern, But Not Emotional Empathy, Predict Sensitivity to Injustice for Others,” Social Neuroscience , 11: 1–14.
  • Deigh, J., 1996. “Empathy and Universalizability,” in Mind and Morals , L. May, M. Friedman and A. Clark (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 199–219.
  • –––, 2011. “Empathy, Justice, and Jurisprudence,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy , 49 (Spindel Supplement): 73–90.
  • –––, 2018. “Is Empathy Required for Making Moral Judgment?,” in Forms of Fellow Feeling: Empathy, Sympathy and Moral Agency , N. Roughley and T. Schramme (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 245–264.
  • Deimling, W., 2017. “Hutchinson’s and Kant’s Critique of Sympathy,” in Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment , E. Robinson and C.W. Suprenant (eds.), New York: Routledge, 55–780.
  • Deonna, J.A., 2007. “The Structure of Empathy,” Journal of Moral Philosophy , 4: 99–116.
  • De Waal, Fr., 2006. Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved , Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
  • –––., 2009. The Age of Empathy: Nature’s Lessons for a Kinder Society , New York: Random House.
  • DeVignemont, F., and T. Singer, 2006. “The Empathic Brain: How, When, and Why?” Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 10: 435–441.
  • Dilthey, W., 1961–. Gesammelte Schriften , 15 vols. Leipzig: Teubner Verlagsgesellschaft.
  • Dray, W., 1957. Laws and Explanation in History , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1995. History as Re-enactment , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Droysen, J.G., 1977. Historik , Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.
  • Dymont, R., 1949. “A Scale of Measurement of Empathic Ability,” Journal of Consulting Psychology , 13: 127–133.
  • Eisenberg, N., 2000a. “Empathy and Sympathy,” M. Lewis and J.M. Haviland-Jones (eds.), Handbook of Emotions , New York/London: Guilford Press, 677–691.
  • –––, 2000b. “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development,” Annual Review of Psychology , 51: 665–697.
  • Eisenberg, N., and J. Strayer (eds.), 1987. Empathy and Its Development , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Eisenberg, N., and P.A. Miller, 1987. “Empathy, Sympathy, and Altruism: Empirical and Conceptual Links,” ed. N. Eisenberg,and J. Strayer, Empathy and Its Development , 292–316. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Eisenberg, N. and R. Fabes, 1998. “Prosocial Development,” W. Damon and N. Eisenberg (eds.), Handbook of Child Psychology (Volume 3: Social, Emotional and Personality Development), 701–778. New York: Wiley.
  • Eisenberg, N., B. Murphy, and S. Shepard, 1997. “The Development of Empathic Accuracy,” in Empathic Accuracy , W. Ickes (ed.), New York/London: Guilford Press, 73–116.
  • Frazer, M., 2010. The Enlightenment of Sympathy: Justice and the Moral Sentiments in the Eighteenth Century and Today , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fricke, C., 2005. “Genesis und Geltung moralischer Normen: Ein Gedankenexperiment von Adam Smith,” in Adam Smith als Moralphilosoph , C. Fricke and H.P. Schütt (eds.), Berlin/New York: DeGruyter, 33–63.
  • Frith, U., and C.D. Frith, 2003. “Development and Neurophysiology of Mentalizing,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Series B, 358: 459–473.
  • Fuchs, T., 2019. “Empathy, Group Identity, and the Mechanisms of Exclusion: An Investigation into the Limits of Empathy,” Topoi , 38: 239–250.
  • Gadamer, H.-G., 1989. Truth and Method , New York: Crossroad Publishing.
  • Gallagher, S., 2012. “Neurons, Neonates, and Narrativ: From Embodied Resonance to Empathic Understanding,” in Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: Motion and Emotion in Intersubjectivity, Consciousness, and Language , A. Foolen, U, Lüdtke, t. Racine and J. Zlatev (eds.), Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 165–196.
  • Gallagher, S., and D. Hutto, 2008. “Understanding Others Through Primary Interaction and Narrative Practice,” in The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity , J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen (eds.), Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 17–38.
  • Gallese, V., 2001. “The ‘Shared Manifold’ Hypothesis: From Mirror Neurons to Empathy,” Journal of Consciousness Studies , 8: 33–50.
  • –––, 2003a. “The Roots of Empathy: The Shared Manifold Hypothesis and the Neural Basis of Intersubjectivity,” Psychopathology , 36: 171–180.
  • –––, 2003b. “The Manifold Nature of Interpersonal Relations: The Quest for a Common Mechanism,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society , 358: 517–528.
  • –––, 2016. “Finding the Body in the Brain: From Simulation Theory to Embodied Simulation,” in Goldman and His Critics , B. McLaughlin and H.K. Kornblith (eds.), Oxford: Wiley, 297–314.
  • Gallese, V., C. Keysers, and G. Rizzolatti, 2004. “A Unifying View of the Basis of Social Cognition,” Trends in Cognitive Science , 8: 396–403.
  • Galinsky, A. and G. Moskowitz, 2001. “Perspective Taking: Decreasing Stereotype Expression, Stereotype Accessibility, and In–Group Favoritism,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 78: 708–724.
  • Gazzola, V., L. Aziz-Zadeh, and C. Keysers, 2006. “Empathy and the Somatotopic Auditory Mirror System in Humans,” Current Biology 16: 1824–1829.
  • Goldie, P., 2000. The Emotions , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011. “Anti-Empathy,” in Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 302–317.
  • Goldman, A., 2002. “Simulation Theory and Mental Concepts,” in Simulation and Knowledge of Action , ed. J. Dokic and J. Proust, 1–19. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
  • –––, 2006. Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2009. “Mirroring, Simulating, and Mindreading,” Mind and Language , 24: 235–252.
  • –––, 2011. “Two Routes to Empathy: Insights from Cognitive Neuroscience,” in Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 31–44.
  • Gordon, Robert M., 1995a. “The Simulation Theory: Objections and Misconceptions,” in Folk Psychology , M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 100–122.
  • –––, 1995b. “Simulation Without Introspection from Me to You,” in Mental Simulation , M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 53–67.
  • –––, 2000. “Sellars’s Rylean Revisited,” Protosoziologie , 14: 102–114.
  • Gopnik, A. and A.N. Meltzoff, 1997. Words, Thoughts and Theories : Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Greif, E. and R. Hogan, 1973. “The Theory and Measurement of Empathy,” Journal of Counseling Psychology , 20: 280–284.
  • Grimm, S., 2016. “How Understanding People Differs from Understanding the Natural World,” Philosophical Issues (Noûs Supplement), 26: 209–225.
  • Grimm, S., C. Baumberger, and S. Ammon, 2017. Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science , New York: Routledge.
  • Grondin, J., 1994. Introduction to Philosophical Hermeneutics , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Halpern, J., 2001. From Detached Concern to Empathy: Humanizing Medical Practice , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Heal, J., 2003. Mind, Reason and Imagination , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Heider, F., 1958: The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations , New York: Wiley.
  • Hempel, C., 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanations , New York: Free Press.
  • Henderson, D., 1993. Interpretation and Explanation in the Human Sciences , Albany: State University of New York Press.
  • –––, 2011. “Let’s Be Flexible: Our Interpretive/Explanatory Toolbox, or In Praise of Using a Range of Tools,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 5: 261–299.
  • Henderson, D., and T. Horgan, 2000. “Simulation and Epistemic Competence,” in Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences , H.H. Kögler and K. Stueber (eds.), Boulder: Westview Press, 119–143.
  • Hickok, G., 2008. “Eight Problems for the Mirror Neuron Theory of Action Understanding in Monkeys and Humans,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 21: 1229–1243.
  • –––, 2014. The Myth of Mirror Neurons: The Real Neuroscience of Cognition and Communication , New York: W.W. Norton and Company.
  • Hoffman, M., 1981. “Is Altruism Part of Human Nature?,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 40: 121–137.
  • –––, 2000. Empathy and Moral Development , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2011. “Empathy, Justice and the Law,” in Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 230–254.
  • –––, 2014. “Empathy, Justice and Social Change,” in Empathy and Morality , H. Maibom (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 71–96.
  • Hogan, R., 1969. “Development of an Empathy Scale,” Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology , 33: 307–316.
  • Hollan, D.W., 2012. “Emerging Issues in the Cross-Cultural Study of Empathy,” Emotion Review , 4: 70–78.
  • Hollan, D.W. and C.J. Throop, 2008. “Whatever Happened to Empathy? Introduction,” Ethos , 36: 385–401.
  • Hollan, D.W. and C.J. Throop, 2011. The Anthropology of Empathy: Experiencing the Lives of Others in Pacific Societies , New York: Berghahn Books.
  • Holz-Ebeling, F. and M. Steinmetz, 1995. “Wie brauchbar sind die vorliegenden Fragebogen zur Messung von Empathie? Kritische Analysen unter Berücksichtigung der Iteminhalte,” Zeitschrift für Differentielle und Diagnostische Psychologie , 16: 11–32.
  • Hume, D., 1739–40 [1978]. A Treatise of Human Nature , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978.
  • –––, 1748 [1983]. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983.
  • Husserl, E., 1931 [1963]. Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge , Gesammelte Werke, vol. 1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1963; translated as Cartesian Meditations , The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969.
  • Hutto, D., 2008. Folk-Psychological Narratives, The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Iacoboni, M., 2011. “Within Each Other: Neural Mechanisms for Empathy in the Primate Brain,”In Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 45–57.
  • Ickes, W., 1993. “Empathic Accuracy,” Journal of Personality 61: 587–610.
  • –––(ed.), 1997. Empathic Accuracy , New York/London: Guilford Press.
  • –––, 2003. Everyday Mindreading , New York. Prometheus Book.
  • Jacob, P., 2008. “What Do Mirror Neurons Contribute to Human Social Cognition?” Mind and Language , 23: 190–223.
  • –––, 2011. “The Direct–Perception Model of Empathy: A Critique,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology , 2: 519–540.
  • Johnson, J., J. Cheek, and R. Smither, 1983. “The Structure of Empathy,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 45: 1299–1312.
  • Jolliffe, D. and D.P. Farrington, 2006. “Development and Validation of the Basic Empathy Scale,” Journal of Adolescence , 29: 589–611.
  • Jordon, R., Amir, D. and P. Bloom, 2016. “Are Empathy and Concern Psychologically Distinct?” Emotion , 16: 1107–1116.
  • Kain, W. and J. Perner, 2003. “Do children with ADHD not need their frontal lobes for theory of mind?: A review of brain imaging and neuropsychological studies,” in The Social Brain: Evolution and Pathology , M. Brüne, H. Ribbert, and W. Schiefenhövel (eds.), Chichester, UK: John Wiley, 197–230.
  • Kauppinen, A., 2014. “Empathy, Emotion Regulation, and Moral Judgment,”in Empathy and Morality , H. Maibom (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 97–121.
  • –––, 2017a. “Empathy and Moral Judgment,”, in The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Empathy , New York: Routledge, 215–226.
  • –––, 2017b. “Sentimentalism, Blameworthiness, and Wrongdoing,” in Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives , R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 133–152.
  • Keen, S., 2007. Empathy and the Novel , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kelly, D., S. Stich, K. Haley, S. Eng, and D. Fessler, 2007. “Harm, Affect, and the Moral/Conventional Distinction,” Mind and Language , 22: 117–131.
  • Kennett, J., 2002. “Autism, Empathy and Moral Agency,” The Philosophical Quarterly , 50: 340–357.
  • –––, 2011. “Imagining Reasons,” Southern Journal of Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), 49: 181–192.
  • Keysers, Chr., 2011. The Empathic Brain: How the Discovery of Mirror Neurons Changes our Understanding of Human Nature , Social Brain Press.
  • Kim, J., 1984. “Self-Understanding and Rationalizing Explanations,” Philosophia Naturalis , 21: 309–320.
  • –––, 1998. “Reasons and the First Person,” in Human Action, Deliberation, and Causation , J. Bransen and St. Cuypers (eds.), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 67–87.
  • Kögler, H.-H. and K. Stueber, 2000. Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences , Boulder: Westview Press.
  • Kteily, N. and E. Bruneau, 2017. “Darker Demons of Our Nature: The Need to (Re-)Focus Attention on Blatant Forms of Dehumanization,” Current Directions in Psychological Science , 26: 487–494.
  • Lamm, C., D. D. Batson, and J. Decety, 2007. “The Neural Substrate of Human Empathy: Effects of Perspective-Taking and Cognitive Appraisal,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 19: 42–58.
  • Lanzoni, S., 2018. Empathy: A History , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Leslie, A.M., R. Mallon, and J.A. DiCorcia, 2006. “Transgressors, Victims, and Cry Babies: Is Basic Moral Judgment Spared in Autism?,” Social Neuroscience , 1: 270–283.
  • Lipps, T., 1903a. “Einfühlung, Innere Nachahmung und Organempfindung,” Archiv für gesamte Psychologie 1: 465–519; translated as “Empathy, Inner Imitation and Sense-Feelings,” in A Modern Book of Esthetics , 374–382. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1979.
  • –––, 1903b. Aesthetik (Volume 1), Hamburg: Voss Verlag.
  • –––, 1905. Aesthetik (Volume 2), Hamburg: Voss Verlag.
  • –––, 1906. “Einfühlung und Ästhetischer Genuß,” Die Zukunft , 16: 100–114.
  • –––, 1907. “Das Wissen von Fremden Ichen,” Psychologische Untersuchungen , 1: 694–722.
  • –––, 1912/13. “Zur Einfühlung,” Psychologische Untersuchungen , 2: 111–491.
  • Maibom, H., 2005: “Moral Unreason: The Case of Psychopathy,” Mind and Language , 20: 237–257.
  • –––, 2007. “The Presence of Others,” Philosophical Studies , 132: 161–190.
  • –––, 2009. “Feeling for Others: Empathy, Sympathy, and Morality” Inquiry , 52: 483–499.
  • ––– (ed.), 2014. Morality and Empathy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2017. “Psychopathy: Morally Incapacitated Persons,” in Handbook of the Philosophy of Medicine , Th. Schramme and S. Edwards (eds.), Berlin/New York: Springer, 1131–1144.
  • Makkreel, R., 2000. “From Simulation to Structural Transposition: A Diltheyan Critique of Empathy and Defense of Verstehen ”. In Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences , H.H. Kögler and K. Stueber (eds.), Boulder: Westview Press, 181–193.
  • Marsh, A., 2014. “Empathy and Moral Deficits in Psychopaths,” in Empathy and Morality , H. Maibom (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 138–154.
  • Matravers, D., 2018. “ The Object of Empathic Emotions,” in Philosophical Perspectives on Empathy: Theoretical Approaches and Empirical Challenges , D. Matravers and A. Waldow (eds.), New York: Routledge, 60–73.
  • May, J., 2018. Regard for Reason in the Moral Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • May, L., M. Friedman, and A. Clark, 1996. Mind and Morals , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • McGeer, V., 2008. “Varieties of Moral Agency: Lessons from Autism,” in Moral Psychology (Volume 3), W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 227–248.
  • Mead. G.H., 1934. Mind, Self, and Society , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Mehrabian, A. and N. Epstein, 1972. “A Measure of Emotional Empathy,” Journal of Personality , 40: 525–543.
  • Mehrabian, A., A.L. Young, and S. Sato, 1988. “Emotional Empathy and Associated Individual Differences,” Current Psychology : Research and Review , 7: 221–240.
  • Meltzoff, A., and R. Brooks, 2001. “‘Like Me’ as a Building Block for Understanding Other Minds: Bodily Acts, Attention, and Intention,” in Intentions and Intentionality , ed. B. Malle, L. Moses and D. Baldwin, 171–191. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Nichols, S., 2001. “Mindreading and the Cognitive Architecture underlying Altruistic Motivation,” Mind & Language , 16: 425–455.
  • –––, 2004. Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundation of Moral Judgment , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nichols, S., and S. Stich, 2003. Mindreading , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Neuberg, S.L., R. Cialdini, S.L. Brown, C. Luce, and B. Sagarin, 1997. “Does Empathy Lead to Anything More Than Superficial Helping?,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73: 510–516.
  • Oxley, J.C., 2011. The Moral Dimensions of Empathy: Limits and Applications in Ethical Theory and Practice , Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Persson, I., and J. Savulescu, 2018. “The Moral Importance of Reflective Empathy,” Neuroethics , 11: 183–193.
  • Prandl, A., 1910. Die Einfühlung , Leipzig: Verlag von Johann Ambrosius Barth.
  • Preston, S., and F. de Waal, 2002a. “Empathy: Its Ultimate and Proximate Bases,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 25: 1–72.
  • –––, 2002b. “Communications of Emotions and the Possibility of Empathy in Animals,” ed. S. Post, L. Underwood, J. Schloss, and W. Hurblut, Altruism and Altruistic Love: Science, Philosophy, and Religion in Dialogue , 284–308. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Prinz, J., 2011a. “Is Empathy Necessary for Morality?” in Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives , A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 211–229.
  • –––, 2011b. “Against Empathy,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy , 49 (Spindel Supplement): 214–233.
  • Ravenscroft, I., 1998. “What is it Like to be Someone Else? Simulation and Empathy,” Ratio , 11: 170–185.
  • Rhodes, M. and L. Chalik, 2013. “Social Categories as Markers of Intrinsic Interpersonal Obligations,” Psychological Science , 26: 999–1006.
  • Rifkin, J., 2009. The Empathic Civilization: The Race to Global Consciousness in a World in Crisis , New York: Tarcher/Penguin.
  • Rizzolatti, G. and L. Craighero, 2004. “The Mirror Neuron System,” Annual Review Neuroscience , 27: 169–192.
  • Rizzolatti, G. and C. Sinigaglia, 2008. Mirrors in the Brain: How our Minds Share Actions and Emotions , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016. “The Mirror Mechanism: A Basic Principle of Brain Function,” Nature Review Neuroscience , 17: 757–765.
  • Rogers, C., 1959. “A Theory of Therapy, Personality, and Interpersonal Relations, as Developed in the Client-Centered Framework,” in S. Koch (ed.), Psychology: A Study of a Science (Vol. 3), New York: McGraw–Hill, 184–256.
  • –––, 1975. “Empathic: An Unappreciated Way of Being,” The Counseling Psychologist , 5: 2–10 (Reprinted in C. Rogers. 1980. A Way of Being , Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 137–164.
  • Roughley, N., 2018. “The Empathy in Moral Obligation: An Excercise in Creature Construction,” in Forms of Fellow Feeling: Empathy, Sympathy and Moral Agency , N. Roughley and T. Schramme (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 265–291.
  • Sayre-McCord, G., 1994. “On Why Hume’s 'General Point of View' Ins’t Ideal—And Shouldn’t Be,” Social Philosophy and Policy , 11: 202–228.
  • –––, 2013. “Hume and Smith on Sympathy, Approbation, and Moral Judgment,” Social Philosophy and Policy , 30: 208–236.
  • Sherman, N., 1998. “Empathy and Imagination,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy , 22: 82–119.
  • Seemann, A., 2011. Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Scheler, M., 1973. Wesen und Form der Sympathie , Bern/München: Francke Verlag; English translation, The Nature of Sympathy , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul 1954.
  • Schleiermacher, Fr., 1998. Hermeneutics and Criticism , edited by A. Bowie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Schopenhauer, A., 1995. On the Basis of Morality , Providence: Berghahn Books.
  • Simmons, A., 2014. “In Defense of the Moral Significance of Empathy,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , 17: 97–111.
  • Singer, T., and C. Lamm, 2009. “The Social Neuroscience of Empathy,” The Year in Cognitive Neuroscience: Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences , 1156, 81–96.
  • Slote, M., 2007. The Ethics of Care and Empathy , London: Routledge.
  • –––, 2010. Moral Sentimentalism , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, A., 1853. The Theory of Moral Sentiments , New York: August M. Kelley Publishers, 1966.
  • Sober, E. and D.S. Wilson, 1998. Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Spinrad, T.L. and N.Eisenberg, 2014. “Empathy and Morality: A Developmental Psychology Perspective,” in Empathy and Morality , H. Maibom (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 59–70.
  • Stein, E., 1917. Zum Problem der Einfühlung , München: Kaffke Verlag, 1980; English translation, E. Stein, On the Problem of Empathy , Washington: ICS Publishers, 1989.
  • Stotland, E., 1969. “Exploratory Investigations of Empathy,” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology , (Vol. 4), L. Berkowitz (ed.), New York/London: Academic Press, 271–314.
  • Stueber, K., 2002. “The Psychological Basis of Historical Explanation: Reenactment, Simulation and the Fusion of Horizons,” History and Theory , 41: 24–42.
  • –––, 2006: Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2008. “Reasons, Generalizations, Empathy, and Narratives: The Epistemic Structure of Action Explanation,” History and Theory , 47: 31–43.
  • –––, 2009. “The Ethical Dimension of Folk-Psychology,” Inquiry , 52: 532–547.
  • –––, 2011a. “Imagination, Empathy, and Moral Deliberation: The Case of Imaginative Resistance,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy , 49 (Spindel Supplement): 156–180.
  • –––, 2011b. “Social Cognition and the Allure of the Second-Person Perspective: In Defense of Empathy and Simulation,” in Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosopy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience , ed. A. Seemann, 265–292. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2011c. “Moral Approval and the Dimensions of Empathy: Comments on Michael Slote’s Moral Sentimentalism ,” Analytic Philosophy , 52: 328–336.
  • –––, 2012a. “Varieties of Empathy, Neuroscience and the Narrativist Challenge to the Theory of Mind Debate,” Emotion Review , 4: 55–63.
  • –––, 2012b.“Understanding versus Explanation: How to Think about the Distinction between the Human and the Natural Sciences,” Inquiry , 55: 17–32.
  • –––, 2017: “Smithian Constructivism: Elucidating the Reality of the Normative Domain,” in Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives , R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 192–209.
  • Taft, R., 1955. “The Ability to Judge People,” Psychological Bulletin , 52: 1–23.
  • Titchener, E. B., 1909: Lectures on the Experimental Psychology of Thought-Processes , New York: Macmillan.
  • Tully, J. (ed.), 1988. Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Turiel, E., 1983. The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality and Convention , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Throop, C.J., 2010. “Latitudes of Loss: On the Vicissitudes of Empathy,” American Ethnologist , 37: 771–782.
  • Vischer, R., 1873. “On the Optical Sense of Form: A Contribution to Aesthetics,” in Empathy, Form, and Space , H.F. Mallgrave and Eleftherios Ikonomou (eds., trans.), Santa Monica, CA: The Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities, 1994, 89–123.
  • Winch, P., 1958. The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy , London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  • Wispe, L., 1986. “The Distinction between Sympathy and Empathy: To Call Forth a Concept a Word is Needed,” in Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 50: 314–321.
  • –––, 1987. “History of the Concept of Empathy,” in Empathy and Its Development , N. Eisenberg and J. Strayer (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 17–37.
  • –––, 1991. The Psychology of Sympathy , New York/London: Plenum Press.
  • Xu, X., X. Zuo, X. Wang, and S. Han, 2009. “Do You Feel My Pain? Racial Group Membership Modulates Empathic Neural Responses,” Journal of Neuroscience , 29: 8525–8529,
  • Zahavi, D., 2001. “Beyond Empathy: Phenomenological Approaches to Intersubjectivity,” Journal of Consciousness Studies , 8. 151–167.
  • –––, 2005. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2010. “Empathy, Embodiment and Interpersonal Understanding: From Lipps to Schutz,” Inquiry , 53: 285–306.
  • Zahavi, D., and S. Overgaard, 2012. “Empathy without Isomorphism: A Phenomenological Account,” in Empathy: From Bench to Bedside , J. Decety (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 3–20.
  • Zaki, J., 2014. “Empathy: A Motivated Account,” Psychological Bulletin , 140: 1608–1647.
  • Zaki, J. and K. Ochsner, 2012. “The Cognitive Neuroscience of Sharing and Understanding Others’ Emotions,” in Empathy: From Bench to Bedside , J. Decety (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 207–226.
  • Zalla, T., L. Barlassina, M. Buon, and M. Leboyer, 2011. “Moral Judment in Adults with Autism Spectrum Disorders,” Cognition , 12: 115–126.
  • Zhou, Q., C. Valiente, and N. Eisenberg, 2003. “Empathy and Its Measurement,” S.J. Lopez and C.R. Snyder (eds.), Positive Psychological Assessment: A Handbook of Models and Measures , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 269–284.

Further Important Surveys of Empathy

  • Maibom, H. (ed.), 2017. The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Empathy , New York: Routledge.
  • Matraver, D., 2017. Empathy , Cambridge: Polity Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Dictionary of the History of Ideas , maintained by The Electronic Text Center at the University of Virginia Library.

Collingwood, Robin George | folk psychology: as mental simulation | hermeneutics | Husserl, Edmund | moral psychology: empirical approaches | moral sentimentalism | other minds | phenomenology

Copyright © 2019 by Karsten Stueber < kstueber @ holycross . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Empathy 101: 3+ Examples and Psychology Definitions

Empathy

Has a book, film, or photograph ever driven you to tears?

Or have you ever felt driven to ease someone else’s emotions?

If you have answered yes to at least one of these, then you have experienced empathy.

Empathy is a complex psychological process that allows us to form bonds with other people. Through empathy, we cry when our friends go through hard times, celebrate their successes, and rage during their times of hardship. Empathy also allows us to feel guilt, shame, and embarrassment, as well as understand jokes and sarcasm.

In this article, we explore empathy, its benefits, and useful ways to measure it. We also look at empathy fatigue – a common experience among clinicians and people in the caring professions – and provide beneficial resources.

Before you continue, we thought you might like to download our three Emotional Intelligence Exercises for free . These science-based exercises will not only enhance your ability to understand and work with your emotions but will also give you the tools to foster the emotional intelligence of your clients, students, or employees.

This Article Contains

What is empathy in psychology, the empathy quotient, 7 real-life examples, is it important 3+ benefits of empathy, empathy vs sympathy and compassion, assessing empathy: 4 helpful questionnaires, a note on empathy fatigue, positivepsychology.com resources, a take-home message.

In psychology, empathy is loosely defined as an ability to understand and experience someone else’s feelings and to adopt someone else’s viewpoint (Colman, 2015). The term ‘empathy’ comes from the German word Einfuhlung, which means “projecting into” (Ganczarek, HĂŒnefeldt, & Belardinelli, 2018) and may explain why empathy is considered the ability to place yourself in someone else’s shoes.

Difficulties with defining empathy

Defining empathy clearly and exhaustively enough to be studied in psychology is difficult. For example, is empathy the ability to understand or feel or share or interpret  someone else’s feelings?

Each of these verbs differs slightly, providing a different meaning to empathy. As a result, the underlying psychological mechanism and part of the brain responsible for empathy also differ.

Part of the difficulty defining empathy is that it comprises multiple components. For example, Hoffman (1987) argued that empathy in children develops across four different stages and that each stage lays down the foundation for the next.

These four stages are:

  • Global empathy or ‘emotion contagion,’ where one person’s emotion evokes the same emotional reaction in another person (or the observer).
  • Attention to others’ feelings, where the observer is aware of another person’s feelings but doesn’t mirror them.
  • Prosocial actions, where the observer is aware of another person’s feelings and behaves in a way to comfort the other person.
  • Empathy for another’s life condition, where the observer feels empathy toward someone else’s broader life situation, rather than their immediate situation right at this instance.

Fletcher-Watson and Bird (2020) provide an excellent overview of the challenges associated with defining and studying empathy. They argue that empathy results from a four-step process:

  • Step 1: Noticing/observing someone’s emotional state
  • Step 2: Correctly interpreting that emotional state
  • Step 3: ‘Feeling’ the same emotion
  • Step 4: Responding to the emotion

Empathy is not achieved if any of these four steps fail.

This multi-component conception of empathy is echoed across other research. For example, Decety and Cowell (2014) also posit that empathy arises from multiple processes interacting with each other.

These processes are:

  • Emotional: The ability to share someone else’s feelings
  • Motivational: The need to respond to someone else’s feelings
  • Cognitive: The ability to take someone else’s viewpoint

Empathy and sadness

Part of this confusion stems from their corresponding definitions.

Empathy is the ability to share someone else’s emotions and perspectives. Emotional intelligence is the ability to understand, interpret, and manage other people’s emotions, as well as your own. This last inclusion – your own emotions – is what distinguishes emotional intelligence from empathy.

The Empathy Quotient is a measurement of empathy (Baron-Cohen & Wheelwright, 2004). It is akin to the Intelligence Quotient (IQ) but is a measure of empathy rather than intelligence. Like IQ, higher scores of the Empathy Quotient are meant to represent higher abilities of empathy.

Importantly, the Empathy Quotient differs from the Emotional Quotient. Emotional Quotient is measured using the BarOn Emotional Quotient-Inventory (Bar-On, 2004) and aims to measure emotional intelligence rather than empathy. It’s easy to confuse them because “EQ” is used to refer to both.

To determine whether the Empathy Quotient is a suitable test of empathy, Baron-Cohen and Wheelwright (2004) administered the measurement to a group of neurotypical people and a group of people diagnosed with Asperger syndrome and compared their scores.

On average, individuals with Asperger syndrome scored significantly lower than neurotypical people. From this study, a score of 30 was determined to be a critical cut-off mark. Scores less than 30 were typically found among the participants with Asperger syndrome. Furthermore, the test-retest reliability of the Empathy Quotient was high, suggesting that the test reliably measures empathy.

3 emotional intelligence exercises

Download 3 Free Emotional Intelligence Exercises (PDF)

These detailed, science-based exercises will help you or your clients understand and use emotions advantageously.

Download 3 Free Emotional Intelligence Tools Pack (PDF)

By filling out your name and email address below.

Since empathy is so complex and involved in so many social interactions, there are many examples of empathy in the real world.

In a discussion with a friend, have you ever felt so moved that you experienced the same emotion that they did? Or maybe a friend shared a cringe-worthy story of sheer humiliation, and that feeling was mirrored in you.

These situations when you experienced the same emotions as your friends are examples of empathy. Other examples of empathy include understanding someone else’s point of view during an argument, feeling guilty when you realize why someone might have misunderstood what you said, or realizing something you said was a faux pas . These scenarios require you to take someone else’s viewpoint.

Some of the best examples of empathy can be found in the work by Oliver Sacks and Atul Gawande. Sacks was a neurologist who had a profound impact through his thoughtful, patient-driven books on the field of psychiatry and neuropsychology.

Atul Gawande is a surgeon who worked with the World Health Organization and has published several books on improving healthcare and healthcare systems. Both authors address their patients in a sensitive, thoughtful manner that evokes a lot of empathy in the reader.

The following books are highly recommended:

  • Awakenings by Oliver Sacks
  • The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat by Oliver Sacks
  • Being Mortal by Atul Gawande

Benefits of empathy

We participate in many scenarios in which we convey and receive information with other people, verbally and nonverbally.

Regardless of whether or not these interactions are important, we have to perceive, interpret, and respond to numerous cues.

Empathy is more than ‘just’ the ability to feel what someone else is feeling. Empathy is an essential skill that allows us to effectively engage with other people in social contexts (Baron-Cohen & Wheelwright, 2004).

Without empathy, we would struggle to:

  • understand other people’s feelings, motivations, and behaviors;
  • respond appropriately to someone else’s feelings; and
  • understand social interactions that rely on subtle behaviors, cues, and social norms, such as jokes, faux pas, and sarcasm.

The ability to respond appropriately to someone else’s emotions is extremely important for forming bonds. Empathy underlines the bond that forms between parent and child (Decety & Cowell, 2014).

Some researchers even consider some aspects of empathy to be a defining feature of humans. Our ability to consider another person’s viewpoint is considered uniquely human (Decety & Cowell, 2014).

Jean Decety and Jason Cowell (2014) argue that empathy is one process that contributes to understanding and engaging in complex social behavior, such as prosocial behavior, which includes volunteering as well as providing care for people who are terminally ill.

Earlier in this article, we mentioned the studies by Baron-Cohen and Wheelwright (2004) in which they compared Empathy Quotient scores between people with Asperger syndrome and neurotypical people.

People on the autism–Asperger spectrum are believed to have a diminished capacity for empathy and, as a result, struggle with social contexts. However, their lower empathy scores do not mean that they are without feeling or should be considered psychopaths (who also have lower scores of empathy).

People on the autism spectrum often report that their intention is not to hurt other people’s feelings, and they feel guilty if they caused someone else’s hurt feelings (Baron-Cohen & Wheelwright, 2004).

Furthermore, people on the autism spectrum often report that they want human connections; however, they struggle to make them because they are not aware of how their behavior affects how other people perceive them (Baron-Cohen & Wheelwright, 2004). This shows how important empathy is in developing relationships and interpreting subtle social cues.

The three terms – empathy, sympathy, and compassion – are often confused with each other, because they are often used when referring to someone else’s feelings. For example, in response to a friend’s bad news, do you feel empathy, sympathy, or compassion? The terms are used in similar contexts, but they refer to different behaviors.

  • From the definitions provided above, empathy involves interpreting, understanding, feeling, and acting on other people’s feelings. Empathy is a multidimensional process and relies on affective, cognitive, behavioral, and moral components (Jeffrey, 2016). Remember, empathy is the ability to adopt someone else’s viewpoint or to put yourself into someone else’s shoes.
  • Sympathy is the feeling of pity for someone else’s misfortune or circumstances.
  • Compassion is the desire and act of wanting to alleviate someone else’s suffering. Compassion includes the affective components of empathy and sympathy, but it is accompanied by an action to change the circumstances of the person who is suffering (Sinclair et al., 2017). A compassionate act can also result in our suffering alongside the other person; this is referred to as co-suffering. Compassion is also linked to altruistic behavior (Jeffrey, 2016).

Examples of Empathy vs Sympathy vs Compassion

To further cement the difference between these three terms, consider the following examples:

Emma relays a recent event where she was extremely embarrassed. As she retells the story, her friend, Tamika, groans and mutters “Oh my word, I would feel so embarrassed. I would want the world to swallow me whole!”

In this example, Tamika doesn’t actually want to disappear into a hole. Instead, she’s correctly understanding and interpreting the situation that Emma found herself in. She is most likely experiencing empathy for Emma’s situation. She is not feeling pity, nor is she acting compassionately.

Jerome’s mother recently suffered a near-fatal heart attack. He listens to his mother retell her sisters about her experience. As she recounts her experience, she starts crying, because she was so afraid, and she realized that she might never see her loved ones again. Jerome starts crying as he listens to his mother.

In this example, Jerome is feeling sympathy (pity) for his mother and what she went through.

On his route to university, Jamal sees the same homeless man every day. The homeless man sits in the same place, regardless of the weather, with a sign next to him that asks for assistance. Jamal decides to donate some of his clothing to the homeless man.

Jamal’s behavior is an act of compassion . By donating his clothing, he is trying to alleviate the homeless man’s suffering. He may also be experiencing sympathy towards the man, but the act of trying to change the man’s situation is an act of compassion.

empathy essay brainly

World’s Largest Positive Psychology Resource

The Positive Psychology Toolkit© is a groundbreaking practitioner resource containing over 500 science-based exercises , activities, interventions, questionnaires, and assessments created by experts using the latest positive psychology research.

Updated monthly. 100% Science-based.

“The best positive psychology resource out there!” — Emiliya Zhivotovskaya , Flourishing Center CEO

Use these questionnaires to determine what your current level of empathy is.

Empathy Quotient

Assessing empathy

The Empathy Questionnaire (EmQue)

The Empathy Questionnaire (EmQue), designed by Rieffe, Ketelaar, and Wiefferink (2010), measures empathy in young children (average age of around 30 months) and reflects Hoffman’s (1987) theory of how empathy developed in children.

The questionnaire comprises three subscales, which map onto the first three stages of empathy development posited by Hoffman (1987). The questionnaire correlates well with other measures that aim to capture similar constructs. You can access this questionnaire on the Academia website .

The Empathy Questionnaire for Children and Adolescents (EmQue-CA)

A similar version of the EmQue also exists for older children. This version is known as the Empathy Questionnaire for Children and Adolescents (EmQue-CA; Overgaauw, Rieffe, Broekhof, Crone, & GĂŒroğlu, 2017).

Unlike the EmQue, the EmQue-CA is a self-report measure. In other words, the adolescents and children must answer how much they agree with each statement, rather than their parents observing their behaviors.

The final version of the EmQue-CA measures the following three subscales: affective empathy, cognitive empathy, and intention to comfort. The 14 questions and the psychometric properties of the questionnaire are reported in the original paper, which can be accessed on the Frontiers in Psychology website as a free downloadable PDF .

The Toronto Empathy Questionnaire (TEQ)

The Toronto Empathy Questionnaire (TEQ) was developed by refining a collection of questionnaires that measure empathy into a core set of questions (Spreng, McKinnon, Mar, & Levine, 2009).

Researchers collected questions from multiple empathy questionnaires, administered these questions to a large sample of students, and then using exploratory factor analysis, refined the questions to a core set of 16.

The questionnaire and scoring rules are described in the appendix of the original paper (Spreng et al., 2009), which can be accessed on the Measurement Instrument Database for the Social Sciences .

Finally, the TEQ and the Empathy Quotient have a strong, positive correlation, confirming that the questions in both measure the same psychological construct.

Empathy is often confused with sympathy, which involves a lack of truly understanding another person’s experience.

For instance, if your friend recently lost their job, expressing sympathy would include feeling sorry for them and wishing them luck finding another job.

In contrast, empathy entails relating to your friend’s frustrations and fears about unemployment and actively experiencing those negative emotions by putting yourself in their shoes.

An example of compassion would be assisting your friend in applying for other jobs and updating their resume.

While empathy and sympathy drive acts of compassion, compassion stands out due to its proactive nature of motivating individuals to alleviate suffering.

Recognizing the distinctions between sympathy, empathy, and compassion can help you adjust your emotional responses when someone is going through hardship, enabling you to provide better support.

Empathy, sympathy and compassion

Feeling empathy is a very useful skill, especially for health professionals such as clinicians, therapists, and psychologists. But the ability to feel empathy for other people comes at the cost of empathy fatigue.

Empathy fatigue refers to the feeling of exhaustion that health professionals experience in response to constantly revisiting their emotional wounds through their clients’ experience (Stebnicki, 2000). For example, a therapist whose client is going through bereavement may be reminded of their own grief and trauma.

By being emotionally available for their client through emotional and stressful periods, the therapist experiences fatigue at a psychological, emotional, and physiological level (Stebnicki, 2000).

Besides manifesting as a sense of fatigue, we can consider empathy fatigue as a form of re-trauma, and as a result, the symptoms resemble that of secondary traumatic stress disorder.

Empathy fatigue in the clinical domain is also referred to as ‘counselor impairment’ because the clinician’s ability to perform their job is impaired (Stebnicki, 2007). An outcome of empathy fatigue is burnout, with a particularly sudden onset (Stebnicki, 2000).

Stebnicki (2007) provides a comprehensive list of strategies that clinicians can use to prevent empathy fatigue:

  • Self-awareness of the symptoms of empathy fatigue
  • Self-care strategies and lifestyle behaviors that protect the clinician from empathy fatigue
  • Using a support group and supervisor during periods of empathy fatigue

Finally, PositivePsychology.com’s post detailing self-care for therapists can be easily adapted to other industries. For example, these tips could be incorporated into a wellness session in the workplace to help prevent empathy fatigue.

empathy essay brainly

17 Exercises To Develop Emotional Intelligence

These 17 Emotional Intelligence Exercises [PDF] will help others strengthen their relationships, lower stress, and enhance their wellbeing through improved EQ.

Created by Experts. 100% Science-based.

Below is a list of four items, each targeting a different aspect of empathy.

To help children better understand what is meant by empathy, we recommend the What is Empathy? worksheet. In this worksheet, children are asked to recall scenarios when they experienced a similar emotion as someone else. Children are also asked to think of reasons why empathy is a good thing and how they can improve their sense of empathy.

To practice looking at things from a fresh perspective, we recommend the 500 Years Ago Worksheet and the Trading Places Worksheet. Both worksheets can be used in group exercises, but only the second one is also appropriate for individual clients.

In five steps, the Listening Accurately Worksheet  lays out an easy-to-follow guide to better develop empathy through active listening .

This worksheet is especially useful for clinicians and health professionals but is also very appropriate for anyone working in a profession where they need to communicate with other people constantly.

If you’re looking for more science-based ways to help others develop emotional intelligence, this collection contains 17 validated EI tools for practitioners. Use them to help others understand and use their emotions to their advantage.

If we show a little tolerance and humility, and if we are willing to stand in the other person’s shoes — as my mom would say — just for a moment, stand in their shoes. Because here’s the thing about life: there’s no accounting for what fate will deal you. Some days, when you need a hand. There are other days when we’re called to lend a hand.

U.S. President Joseph R. Biden, Jr., Inauguration speech

And that is what empathy is: being able to put yourself in someone else’s shoes. Humans are social creatures, and empathy is an important skill. Without empathy, we will struggle to connect and form bonds. Underdeveloped empathy results in awkward social interactions, which can also weaken social bonds.

No man is an island, entire of itself; every man is a piece of the continent, a part of the main.

By connecting, by understanding, by having empathy, we can all stand together, lend a hand when needed, and be given a hand when we, in turn, may need it.

We hope you enjoyed reading this article. Don’t forget to download our three Emotional Intelligence Exercises for free .

  • Bar-On, R. (2004). The Bar-On Emotional Quotient Inventory (EQ-i): Rationale, description and summary of psychometric properties. In G. Geher (Ed.),  Measuring emotional intelligence: Common ground and controversy (pp. 115–145). Nova Science Publishers.
  • Baron-Cohen, S., & Wheelwright, S. (2004). The Empathy Quotient: An investigation of adults with Asperger syndrome or high functioning autism, and normal sex differences. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders , 34 (2), 163–175.
  • Colman, A. M. (2015). A dictionary of psychology . Oxford University Press.
  • Decety, J., & Cowell, J. M. (2014). The complex relation between morality and empathy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 18 , 337–339.
  • Fletcher-Watson, S., & Bird, G. (2020). Autism and empathy: What are the real links?  Autism ,  24 (1), 3–6.
  • Ganczarek, J., HĂŒnefeldt, T., & Belardinelli, M. O. (2018). From “EinfĂŒhlung” to empathy: Exploring the relationship between aesthetic and interpersonal experience.  Cognitive Processing ,  19 (4), 141–145.
  • Gawande, A. (2017).  Being mortal: Medicine and what matters in the end. Picador.
  • Hoffman, M. L. (1987). The contribution of empathy to justice and moral judgment. In N. Eisenberg & J. Strayer (Eds.), Cambridge studies in social and emotional development. Empathy and its development (pp. 47–80). Cambridge University Press.
  • Jeffrey, D. (2016). Empathy, sympathy and compassion in healthcare: Is there a problem? Is there a difference? Does it matter? Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine , 109 (12), 446–452.
  • John Donne. (2020, October 17). Wikiquote . Retrieved January 20, 2021, from https://en.wikiquote.org/w/index.php?title=John_Donne&oldid=2878168
  • Overgaauw, S., Rieffe, C., Broekhof, E., Crone, E. A., & GĂŒroğlu, B. (2017). Assessing empathy across childhood and adolescence: Validation of the Empathy Questionnaire for Children and Adolescents (EmQue-CA). Frontiers in Psychology , 8 , Article 870.
  • Rieffe, C., Ketelaar, L., & Wiefferink, C. H. (2010). Assessing empathy in young children: Construction and validation of an Empathy Questionnaire (EmQue). Personality and Individual Differences , 49 (5), 362–367.
  • Sacks, O. (1998).  The man who mistook his wife for a hat: And other clinical tales. Touchstone.
  • Sacks, O. W. (2011).  Awakenings (New ed.). Picador.
  • Sinclair, S., Beamer, K., Hack, T. F., McClement, S., Raffin Bouchal, S., Chochinov, H. M., & Hagen, N. A. (2017). Sympathy, empathy, and compassion: A grounded theory study of palliative care patients’ understandings, experiences, and preferences. Palliative Medicine , 31 (5), 437–447.
  • Spreng, R. N., McKinnon, M. C., Mar, R. A., & Levine, B. (2009). The Toronto Empathy Questionnaire: Scale development and initial validation of a factor-analytic solution to multiple empathy measures. Journal of Personality Assessment , 91 (1), 62–71.
  • Stebnicki, M. A. (2000). Stress and grief reactions among rehabilitation professionals: Dealing effectively with empathy fatigue. Journal of Rehabilitation , 66 (1).
  • Stebnicki, M. A. (2007). Empathy fatigue: Healing the mind, body, and spirit of professional counselors. American Journal of Psychiatric Rehabilitation , 10 (4), 317–338.

' src=

Share this article:

Article feedback

What our readers think.

Adam

Im positive that the origin of the word ’empathy’ comes from Greek, with ‘pathos’ being an umbrella word for emotions (sympathy, apathy, antipathy, and from there passion, compassion etc).

Jack Milgram

It’s important to mention that empathy is not a sign of a weak personality. I did a huge work before I could finally cry when touched by my friend’s story. Because “men shouldn’t show their tears in public.” But don’t you dare tell me how I should react! 😀

Let us know your thoughts Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published.

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Related articles

Empathy Sympathy

Understanding Empathy vs. Sympathy: What’s the Difference?

Empathy and sympathy go to the core of what it means to be human. We are a social and highly cooperative animal that depends on [...]

Compassion Fatigue

What Is Compassion Fatigue? 24 Causes & Symptoms Explained

Are you in a caring profession? If so, do you ever feel preoccupied with the suffering of the people you work with? In a helping [...]

Inner critic

Living With the Inner Critic: 8 Helpful Worksheets (+ PDF)

We all know this voice in our head that constantly criticizes, belittles, and judges us. This voice has many names: inner critic, judge, saboteur, the [...]

Read other articles by their category

  • Body & Brain (52)
  • Coaching & Application (39)
  • Compassion (23)
  • Counseling (40)
  • Emotional Intelligence (21)
  • Gratitude (18)
  • Grief & Bereavement (18)
  • Happiness & SWB (40)
  • Meaning & Values (26)
  • Meditation (16)
  • Mindfulness (40)
  • Motivation & Goals (41)
  • Optimism & Mindset (29)
  • Positive CBT (28)
  • Positive Communication (23)
  • Positive Education (36)
  • Positive Emotions (32)
  • Positive Leadership (16)
  • Positive Parenting (14)
  • Positive Psychology (21)
  • Positive Workplace (35)
  • Productivity (16)
  • Relationships (46)
  • Resilience & Coping (38)
  • Self Awareness (20)
  • Self Esteem (37)
  • Strengths & Virtues (29)
  • Stress & Burnout Prevention (33)
  • Theory & Books (42)
  • Therapy Exercises (37)
  • Types of Therapy (54)

empathy essay brainly

Download 3 Free Self-Compassion Tools Pack (PDF)

3 Self-Compassion Tools (PDF)

Pamela D. Brown Ph.D.

What Does It Mean to Have Empathy?

How can we cultivate empathy in children.

Updated June 4, 2024 | Reviewed by Monica Vilhauer

  • The Importance of Empathy
  • Take our Empathy Test
  • Find a therapist near me
  • Empathy is the ability to understand and share someone else’s feelings and respond in a compassionate way.
  • People who demonstrate empathy tend to be more resilient and draw others to them.
  • We demonstrate greater empathy towards those with whom we believe we share similarities, even small ones.

Takasuu/Getty Images

What to do this summer? —Develop your child's empathy

As another school year ends, many parents wonder how to make the best use of the summer months. Sometimes, tutoring or targeted work addressing an area with room for improvement is the answer. Maybe a student is below his peers in math, or could solidify a critical skill area. I have known decent writers in high school who seek out a writing course to finesse their essay writing skills so college won’t feel so demanding. Summer can also be a period to focus on softer skills that take time to develop and that may be difficult to focus on during the school year, when so much is going on, especially for parents who work and who have more than one child.

Empathy is one of these soft skills. It draws others to us and contributes to our resilience , making us better able to recover in the face of adversity. Social support keeps us from falling as far so that we have less to bounce back from. To be empathic, one needs to read and feel other people's feelings (affective/emotional empathy) and to understand other people's perspectives (cognitive empathy).

Emotional Empathy

The capacity for emotional empathy partly comes from our experiences. It's hard to imagine anyone's distress if we have never suffered distress of our own. This is not to say that we must have had the exact same experiences as others; we can recognize the emotion of sadness even when it is caused by events we have never endured. For example, a person who has lost a grandparent can recognize the pain of a peer whose best friend moves far away.

Cognitive Empathy

Another aspect of empathy involves understanding the other person's perspective—how they see the situation that led to their particular feelings. Often, in order to be cognitively empathetic ,` we need to know something about another person’s historical experiences to understand how an event is likely to be felt by that person.

Konstantin Pelikh/Free For Canva for Education

The Role of Coping in Promoting Empathy

Those well equipped to cope with unpleasant feelings of their own are not surprisingly able to and comfortable supporting a suffering peer. If we are not good at dealing with our own disappointment or sadness, it is less likely we will be inclined to tolerate someone else's reactions to misfortune. And because we don’t like enduring suffering, we are more likely to pull away from another sufferer if there is no obvious solution for changing the situation. Distress that we feel we have no capacity to change or resolve can feel especially threatening, even if it is experienced by another person.

Not surprisingly, children whose parents have helped them learn to deal with their unpleasant emotions are more likely to recognize such emotions in their friends and are less likely to shy away from those displaying emotional distress. They are actually more likely to approach this person and offer consolation, in part because the other person's emotion is not threatening to them. They have learned that it is not something that is impossible to change – that their emotions are not permanently debilitating. They recognize a circumstance that can be coped with and modified, and they are met with extreme gratitude from the person receiving their support.

Children who can cope with their difficult emotions are likely able to do so because some adult has coached them along the way by recognizing or reading their emotions and by acknowledging that how they feel is reasonable given their perspective. If these parents also remind their children that their emotion is not a permanent state and explain how they might temper them, the unpleasantness can seem less intolerable. Those children who can look at situations with less anxiety and prediction of doom are not surprisingly those who are also more likely to take healthy risks. They have more confidence that they can survive or cope with possible unpleasant outcomes. Children without these coping skills, on the other hand, will refrain from engaging in anything involving risk because if the result is less than desirable, they will feel unable to cope with its resulting unpleasantness.

How to Cultivate Coping

You can teach your children to cope by coaching them and having conversations about feelings, highlighting how our feelings are interconnected with our perspectives about situations, and how past experiences can drive our perspectives. You can also soften the impact of negative feelings by sharing examples of how you have coped with your own unpleasant feelings, giving your children more tools with which to deal with their own unpleasant feelings.

How to Cultivate Affective Empathy

When you see your children attempt to soothe someone else's feelings, praise their social awareness as well as their effort to make the other person feel better. Do this over and over again, because that's how important lessons are learned. You can also point out to them the receptivity of those they help, highlighting how much your children’s efforts to help soothe others were appreciated, even if all they did was sit with them in their moment of disappointment or discomfort.

empathy essay brainly

One more way to foster empathy involves inviting your children to imagine how another person is likely to feel, especially as a consequence of your children’s behavior. It should not be surprising that it is easier for people to be mean to those with whom they feel little connection. If we can create connection by highlighting similarities – even small ones – children, as well as adults, are less likely to engage in hurtful behavior towards another person.

Devonyu/Getty Images Pro

How to Cultivate Cognitive Empathy

We can coach perspective-taking by simply asking children to consider how another person may feel in a given situation. An easy example is asking them to read the faces of characters in books or shows they are watching and to explain why they think this. You can foster their flexibility of thought by imagining alternate situations so your children can realize how our different experiences can change how we feel and think about different situations. You can also do this in conversations discussing one of your own friends or co-workers.

Similarity breeds empathy, not contempt, and this is partly why diversity and inclusion work can be so helpful. Highlighting for children the commonalities they share with others makes them much less likely to engage in biased, discriminatory, or hurtful behavior. This kind of work is essential because there are added influences of in-group bias , as well as the stereotypes children are often exposed to in social media . We know from research that even brief coaching in empathy can produce visible improvements, and that these improvements in handling frustration can be lasting.

Thinglass/Getty Images Pro

Final Thoughts

Even brief coaching can produce noticeable improvements and they can be lasting. Practice reading faces of characters in books or other media. Contemplate what others can be thinking in different situations and the underlying reasons why. Share how you cope. Praise your children when they think about others’ feelings and perhaps even more importantly, soothe someone they believe is in distress. Do this over and over and over again, because that’s how we learn any important lesson.

Pamela D. Brown Ph.D.

Pamela D. Brown, Ph.D., is a licensed psychologist, certified school psychologist, and licensed professional counselor with over 20 years of professional experience.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Online Therapy
  • United States
  • Brooklyn, NY
  • Chicago, IL
  • Houston, TX
  • Los Angeles, CA
  • New York, NY
  • Portland, OR
  • San Diego, CA
  • San Francisco, CA
  • Seattle, WA
  • Washington, DC
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Self Tests NEW
  • Therapy Center
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

July 2024 magazine cover

Sticking up for yourself is no easy task. But there are concrete skills you can use to hone your assertiveness and advocate for yourself.

  • Emotional Intelligence
  • Gaslighting
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience

Empathy: What It Is, Why It Matters, and How You Can Improve

Jump to section, what is empathy, different types of empathy, why is empathy important, are people born with empathy or can it be taught, how to improve your level of empathy.

empathy essay brainly

Did you know that 98% of people have the ability to empathize with others ? The few exceptions are psychopaths, narcissists, and sociopaths which are people who are unable to understand or relate to other people's feelings and emotions.

Other groups of people that might struggle understanding other people's emotions are those who are on the Autism Spectrum. However, many people feel that people on the Autism Spectrum are still capable of relating to other people's emotions , although perhaps not in the traditional way.

While a large majority of the population is capable of empathy, sometimes the practice of it is limited. But what is empathy, and why is it important?

Can empathy be developed, or are we born with a certain amount? Are some people just naturally better at empathizing? Is it really as important as some people say it is to practice empathy?

Let's dive in.

empathy essay brainly

In simple terms, empathy is the ability to understand things from another person's perspective. It's the ability to share someone else's feelings and emotions and understand why they're having those feelings.

Many famous people have talked about the importance of understanding and empathy.

Maya Angelou once said, "I think we all have empathy. We may not have enough courage to display it."

Albert Einstein said, "Peace cannot be kept by force; it can only be achieved by understanding."

Former President Barack Obama has said, "The biggest deficit that we have in our society and in the world right now is an empathy deficit. We are in great need of people being able to stand in somebody else’s shoes and see the world through their eyes."

At the memorial service for the five police officers who lost their lives in Dallas in 2016, former President George W. Bush said, "At our best, we practice empathy, imagining ourselves in the lives and circumstances of others. This is the bridge across our nation's deepest divisions."

In an attempt to define what empathy is, people have created different categories of empathy. According to psychologists Daniel Goleman and Paul Ekman , there are three types of empathy: cognitive, emotional, and compassionate.

  • Cognitive empathy. Cognitive empathy is the ability to understand how someone else feels and to work out what they might be thinking.
  • Emotional empathy or Affective empathy. Emotional empathy refers to the ability to share another person's emotions. This would mean when you see someone else who is sad, it makes you feel sad.
  • Compassionate empathy or Empathic Concern. Compassionate empathy is when you take feelings to actions. It goes beyond understanding and relating to other people's situations, and pushed an individual to do something.

RELATED : How to Become a Better Communicator

empathy essay brainly

Empathy is important in almost every aspect of daily life. It allows us to have compassion for others, relate to friends, loved ones, co-workers, and strangers, and it has a large benefit impact on the world.

In Personal Life

How does empathy help in a person's personal life?

Healthy relationships require nurture, care, and understanding. A friendship or romantic relationship that lacks empathy and understanding will soon flounder. When people only think of their own interests, the other people in the relationships will suffer.

If one spouse in a marriage forgoes seeing things from the other's perspective, they will likely have marital issues. No two people are ever going to think exactly alike, and no two people are going to have the same experiences. Both people in a relationship bring their own ideas, life experiences, and struggles. Without taking the time to try to relate to one another's feelings and perspectives, people in relationships will likely feel unloved and uncared for.

In Work Life

In what was is empathy important in the workplace ?

For many people, a workplace is a place for teamwork. For things that require a group effort, it's extremely important to take the time to relate to co-workers. Even if people are not specifically working on one project, it is still important to get along with fellow workers. Using empathy is a vital part of a smooth working relationship. Without it, it's much easier to fall into disputes and disagreements.

It is also highly important for management to use empathy. Bosses who lack empathy are likely to subject their employees to unfair practices. Managers who are without empathy may push employees to work beyond what is healthy and reasonable or may be unduly harsh when an employee makes a mistake.

Higher amounts empathy in the workplace have been linked to increased performance, increased sales, and better leadership abilities.

For the World

How does empathy impact the world?

Empathy from a global perspective is infinitely important, especially when it leads to compassion. This type of empathy pushes people to dive in and help when there are major disasters. People are willing to help out others that they have never met because they know that they too would need help if things were reversed.

Without compassionate empathy, the world would be a much darker and less functional place to live.

While there is some evidence that the ability to empathize is traced to genetic predisposition, it's also true that empathy is a skill that can be increased or decreased.

One of the most effective ways for someone to become empathic is for them to be trained as children. Empathy is a part of education known as "emotional intelligence." Teaching children to think of the way that other people feel is a good way of helping them develop empathy.

If a child hurts another child or teases them, it's helpful to ask the child how they think they made the other one feel. You can ask them how they would feel if someone had treated them that way. Would they like to be teased or hurt? Would they be sad or angry if someone had treated them poorly?

This line of thought can also be used for positive things. For example, sharing is an important part of a young child's education. Children are often taught to share because they like it when others share with them. It's easy to teach children to treat others with kindness because they too would like to be treated kindly.

While it is easier to train a person from childhood to be empathic, it is also possible for adults to increase their levels of empathy. Below are some ways that will help improve a person's empathy.

Read Literary Fiction

Believe it or not, reading fiction can actually increase your empathy. New studies show that when people read fiction, their brains really feel like they're entering a new world . For example, researchers from the University of Buffalo studied participants who had read Twilight and Harry Potter. What they discovered is that people self-identified as vampires and wizards respectively .

The reason this discovery matters is because it shows that people are able to identify with people and groups that are actually outside of themselves. To put this into a non-fantasy application, it shows that people can relate to people who live lives that are entirely different than their own. For example, people from the United States could read a book about a person in China and learn to identify with someone on the other side of the planet.

In an article about this study, The Guardian writes , "In fiction…we are able to understand characters’ actions from their interior point of view, by entering into their situations and minds, rather than the more exterior view of them that we usually have." In other words, where we would ordinarily not have access to another person's thoughts, literature gives us a window into the inner thinkings of other people.

RELATED : Master the Art of Storytelling

Listening to others is a very good way of developing empathy. When we take the time to listen to the things that other people are telling us it is an easy way of understanding how they think and feel.

Listening is best achieved when we set aside our own thoughts and opinions and carefully think about what another person is saying. We can also do a better job of listening when we set aside distractions like cell phones or tablets. When we give our undivided attention to others we will make them feel like they are cared for and it gives us an opportunity to truly understand their point of view.

Attempt to Understand People with Differing Opinions and Beliefs

For many, it is much easier to identify with people who are in our "in-group." In other words, it's far easier to trust or understand people who we think are like us. This type of thinking can be inhibiting in a diverse workplace, or it may suppress compassionate empathy for those outside of our own communities.

To challenge this type of thinking, it's important to take the time to understand people who are different. To expand empathy, a person might have to challenge pre-conceived notions and biases and consider another person's point of view.

This can also be achieved be people widening their circle and becoming friends with people they might not ordinarily spend time with. They may be surprised to find that they have more in common than they first believed, and it is even more likely that they will broaden their ability for empathy.

Recent Articles

empathy essay brainly

Who’s Sorry Now? 5 Things to Say Instead of Apologizing

Unfortunately, even those with advanced degrees in communications are often guilty of saying "I'm sorry" repeatedly in their personal and professional interactions. Examples abound: apologizing profusely when it takes a few hours to answer a text or email; offering up a hasty mea culpa when you accidentally bump someone in…

empathy essay brainly

Relationships 101: 3 Ways a Communications Degree Helps Your Personal Life

Communications, at its essence, is the study of human interaction and expression. Students pursuing a…

empathy essay brainly

Keys to Being a Better Public Speaker and Beating Your Anxiety

At some point in each of our lives, we will be required to give a…

Free Speech Sign

What Is The Current State Of Free Speech In The United States?

Free speech may be something that we take for granted in the United States, but…

empathy essay brainly

Speaking The Unspoken: How The Wordless Art of Body Language Can Make You A Master of Communication

Are you a good communicator? Clear speaker? Is your grasp of the English language better…

Man Stressed at Work

Using Key Communication Skills To Manage Stress

Stress is something that happens to almost every person from time to time. It is…

empathy essay brainly

Careers for Master’s in Communication Graduates

A master's degree in communication opens the door to a variety of career possibilities across…

empathy essay brainly

Let’s Talk: How To Be A Better Communicator

Communication – it makes the world go round, right? Clear communication is important in almost…

empathy essay brainly

YouTube Shooting Prompts Increased Need for Crisis Communication Experts

The recent tragic shooting at the Silicon Valley headquarters of Google-owned YouTube has highlighted the…

empathy essay brainly

Crises on Campuses Call for Better Communication Between Key Leaders

The news headlines confirm that crises are a sad fact of college life, and no…

Home — Essay Samples — Life — Emotions & Feelings — Empathy

one px

Empathy Essays

Hook examples for empathy essays, anecdotal hook.

"As I witnessed a stranger's act of kindness towards a struggling neighbor, I couldn't help but reflect on the profound impact of empathy—the ability to connect with others on a deeply human level."

Rhetorical Question Hook

"What does it mean to truly understand and share in the feelings of another person? The concept of empathy prompts us to explore the complexities of human connection."

Startling Statistic Hook

"Studies show that empathy plays a crucial role in building strong relationships, fostering teamwork, and reducing conflicts. How does empathy contribute to personal and societal well-being?"

"'Empathy is seeing with the eyes of another, listening with the ears of another, and feeling with the heart of another.' This profound quote encapsulates the essence of empathy and its significance in human interactions."

Historical Hook

"From ancient philosophies to modern psychology, empathy has been a recurring theme in human thought. Exploring the historical roots of empathy provides deeper insights into its importance."

Narrative Hook

"Join me on a journey through personal stories of empathy, where individuals bridge cultural, social, and emotional divides. This narrative captures the essence of empathy in action."

Psychological Impact Hook

"How does empathy impact mental health, emotional well-being, and interpersonal relationships? Analyzing the psychological aspects of empathy adds depth to our understanding."

Social Empathy Hook

"In a world marked by diversity and societal challenges, empathy plays a crucial role in promoting understanding and social cohesion. Delving into the role of empathy in society offers important insights."

Empathy in Literature and Arts Hook

"How has empathy been depicted in literature, art, and media throughout history? Exploring its representation in the creative arts reveals its enduring significance in culture."

Teaching Empathy Hook

"What are effective ways to teach empathy to individuals of all ages? Examining strategies for nurturing empathy offers valuable insights for education and personal growth."

The Power of Empathy and Acceptance in R.j. Palacio’s "Wonder"

The value of my life: personal view, made-to-order essay as fast as you need it.

Each essay is customized to cater to your unique preferences

+ experts online

My Empathetic Self: an Exploration of Empathy

How empathy and understanding others is important for our society, the key components of empathy, importance of the empathy in my family, let us write you an essay from scratch.

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

The Importance of Promoting Empathy in Children

Steps for developing empathy in social situations, the impacts of digital media on empathy, the contributions of technology to the decline of human empathy, get a personalized essay in under 3 hours.

Expert-written essays crafted with your exact needs in mind

The Role of Empathy in Justice System

Importance of empathy for blind people, the most effective method to tune in with empathy in the classroom, thr way acts of kindness can change our lives, the power of compassion and its main aspects, compassion and empathy in teaching, acts of kindness: importance of being kind, the concept of empathy in "do androids dream of electric sheep", the vital values that comprise the definition of hero, critical analysis of kwame anthony appiah’s theory of conversation, development of protagonist in philip k. novel "do androids dream of electric sheep", talking about compassion in 100 words, barbara lazear aschers on compassion, my purpose in life is to help others: helping behavior, humility and values, adolescence stage experience: perspective taking and empathy, random act of kindness, helping others in need: importance of prioritizing yourself, toni cade bambara the lesson summary, making a positive impact on others: the power of influence.

Empathy is the capacity to understand or feel what another person is experiencing from within their frame of reference, that is, the capacity to place oneself in another's position.

Types of empathy include cognitive empathy, emotional (or affective) empathy, somatic empathy, and spiritual empathy.

Empathy-based socialization differs from inhibition of egoistic impulses through shaping, modeling, and internalized guilt. Empathetic feelings might enable individuals to develop more satisfactory interpersonal relations, especially in the long-term. Empathy-induced altruism can improve attitudes toward stigmatized groups, and to improve racial attitudes, and actions toward people with AIDS, the homeless, and convicts. It also increases cooperation in competitive situations.

Empathetic people are quick to help others. Painkillers reduce one’s capacity for empathy. Anxiety levels influence empathy. Meditation and reading may heighten empathy.

Relevant topics

  • Responsibility
  • Forgiveness
  • About Myself

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

empathy essay brainly

  • Health Tech
  • Health Insurance
  • Medical Devices
  • Gene Therapy
  • Neuroscience
  • H5N1 Bird Flu
  • Health Disparities
  • Infectious Disease
  • Mental Health
  • Cardiovascular Disease
  • Chronic Disease
  • Alzheimer's
  • Coercive Care
  • The Obesity Revolution
  • The War on Recovery
  • Adam Feuerstein
  • Matthew Herper
  • Jennifer Adaeze Okwerekwu
  • Ed Silverman
  • CRISPR Tracker
  • Breakthrough Device Tracker
  • Generative AI Tracker
  • Obesity Drug Tracker
  • 2024 STAT Summit
  • All Summits
  • STATUS List
  • STAT Madness
  • STAT Brand Studio

Don't miss out

Subscribe to STAT+ today, for the best life sciences journalism in the industry

Can AI help ease medicine’s empathy problem?

Doctors often fail to express empathy. artificial intelligence — done right — might be able to help them.

  • Manage alerts for this article
  • Email this article
  • Share this article

A realistic image of a female doctor created using generative AI to illustrate how AI doctors on screen may be used for healthcare in the future.

By Evan Selinger and Thomas Carroll

Aug. 15, 2024

Rochester Institute of Technology and University of Rochester Medical Center

Modern medicine has an empathy problem. Artificial intelligence — done right — might be able to help ease it.

Despite the proliferation of communication training programs over the past decade or two, doctors often fail to express empathy, especially in stressful moments when patients and their families are struggling to hear bad news and make difficult decisions. Since empathy has been shown to enhance what patients understand and how much they trust their medical team, falling short compromises the quality of patient care.

advertisement

Can AI help? That might sound like an ironic question, because doctors who struggle to express empathy can come across as robotic. Yet researchers and health care professionals are increasingly asking it, and not just because we’re living through an AI hype cycle .

One reason for the growing interest in AI to help solve medicine’s empathy problem is that this aspect of medical care has proven particularly hard to improve. This isn’t surprising, given that physicians face ever-increasing pressures to quickly see large numbers of patients while finding themselves drowning in paperwork and a myriad of administrative duties. These taxing conditions lead to both a lack of time and, perhaps more importantly, a lack of emotional energy. An American Medical Association report indicated that 48% of doctors experienced burnout last year .

Given the magnitude of the empathy problem and its significant clinical and ethical stakes, various possible uses of AI are being explored. None of them are likely to be silver bullets and, while each is well-intentioned, the entire endeavor is fraught with risks.

One rather extreme option has been suggested by Dr. Arthur Garson Jr., a member of the National Academy of Medicine and a clinical professor of health systems and population health sciences the University of Houston. He urges us to prepare for a time when some human doctors are replaced with AI avatars . Garson thinks it’s possible, even likely, that AI-powered avatars displayed on computer screens could be programmed to look “exactly like a physician” and have “in-depth conversations” with “the patient and family” that are customized to provide “highly appropriate reactions” to a patient’s moods and words.

Whether AI will ever get this advanced raises tricky questions about the ethics of empathy, including the risk of creating negative dehumanizing effects for patients because, for the foreseeable future, computer programs can’t experience empathy . To be sure, not all human doctors who sound empathetic truly feel that way in the moment. Nevertheless, while doctors can’t always control their own feelings, they can recognize and respond appropriately to patients’ emotions, even in the midst of trying circumstances.

Simulated AI “doctors,” no matter how apparently smart, cannot truly care about patients unless they somehow become capable of having the human experience of empathy. Until that day comes — and it may never arise — bot-generated phrases like “I’m sorry to inform you” seem to cheapen the very idea of empathy.

A more moderate vision revolves around various applications of generative AI to support doctors’ communication with patients in real time. Anecdotal evidence suggests this use of this technology is promising, like Dr. Joshua Tamayo-Sarver’s moving account of how ChatGPT saved the day in a California emergency department when he struggled to find the right words to connect with a patient’s distraught family. Preliminary academic research, like a much-discussed article in JAMA Internal Medicine, also suggests generative AI programs based on large language models can effectively simulate empathetic discourse.

Another recent study , however, suggests that while the content of an empathic message matters, so does the messenger’s identity. People rate AI-generated empathic statements as better on average than human-generated ones if they don’t know who or what wrote them. But the machine’s advantage disappears once the recipient learns that the words had been generated by a bot.

In a forthcoming book, “Move Slow and Upgrade,” one of us (E.S.) proposes the following possibility: integrating a version of generative AI into patient portals to help doctors sound more empathetic. Patients see portals as a lifeline, but doctors spend so much time fielding inbox messages that the correspondence contributes to their burnout . Perhaps a win-win is possible. Doctors might improve patient satisfaction and reduce the number of follow-up questions patients ask by pushing an empathy button that edits their draft messages.

While this application of AI-generated empathy is promising in a number of ways, it also runs many risks even if the obvious challenges are resolved, like the technology consistently performs well, is routinely audited, is configured to be HIPAA compliant, neither doctors nor patients are forced to use it, and doctors use it transparently and responsibly. Many tricky issues would still remain. For example, how can doctors use AI quickly and oversee its outputs without placing too much trust in the technology’s performance? What happens if the technology creates a multiple persona problem, where a doctor sounds like a saint online but is a robot in person? And how can a new form of AI dependence be created to avoid further deterioration of human communication?

Some visions capitalize on AI’s potential to enhance doctors’ communication skills. For example, one of us (T.C.) is involved with the SOPHIE Project , an initiative at the University of Rochester to create an AI avatar trained to portray a patient and provide personalized feedback. It could help doctors improve their ability to appropriately express empathy. Preliminary data are promising, although it is too soon to draw firm conclusions, and further clinical trials are ongoing.

This approach has the advantages of being reproducible, scalable, and relatively inexpensive. It will, however, likely have many of the same limitations as traditional, human-actor-based communication training courses. For example, on the individual level, communication skills tend to degrade over time, requiring repeated training. Another issue is that the doctors who most need communication training may be least likely to participate in it. It is also unrealistic to expect SOPHIE-like training programs to overcome system-level stresses and dysfunction, which are a major contributor to the empathy problem in the first place.

Because technology changes so quickly, now is the time to have thoughtful and inclusive conversations about the possibilities we’ve highlighted here. While the two of us don’t have all the answers, we hope discussions about AI and empathic communication are guided by an appreciation that both the messages and the messengers matter. Focusing too much on what AI can do can lead to overestimating the value of its outputs and undervaluing essential relationships of care — relationships that, at least for the foreseeable future, and perhaps fundamentally, can occur only between human beings. At the same time, prematurely concluding that AI can’t help may unnecessarily contribute to preserving a dysfunctional system that leaves far too many patients seeing doctors as robotic.

Evan Selinger, Ph.D., is a professor of philosophy at Rochester Institute of Technology and the co-author, with Albert Fox Cahn, of the forthcoming book “ Move Slow and Upgrade: The Power of Incremental Innovation” (Cambridge University Press). Thomas Carroll, M.D., Ph.D., is an associate professor of medicine at the University of Rochester Medical Center.

Letter to the editor

Have an opinion on this essay? Submit a letter to the editor .

About the reporting

STAT’s investigation is based on interviews with nearly 100 people around the country, including incarcerated patients and grieving families, prison officials, and legal and medical experts. Reporter Nicholas Florko also filed more than 225 public records requests and combed through thousands of pages of legal filings to tell these stories. His analysis of deaths in custody is based on a special data use agreement between STAT and the Department of Justice.

You can read more about the reporting for this project and the methodology behind our calculations.

The series is the culmination of a reporting fellowship sponsored by the Association of Health Care Journalists and supported by The Commonwealth Fund.

Evan Selinger

Thomas Carroll

More on Long Covid

empathy essay brainly

STAT Plus: As Humira biosimilars take over the market, CVS has created a new ploy: the drug ‘rebate credit’

empathy essay brainly

The smartest thinkers in life sciences on what's happening — and what's to come

Your data will be processed in accordance with our Privacy Policy and Terms of Service . You may opt out of receiving STAT communications at any time.

ebook-image

A new era for drug development and research

Recommended

empathy essay brainly

HHS says it is working to stop the climate crisis. But it’s really just climate washing

empathy essay brainly

Ultra-processed foods: the tobacco of the 21st century?

empathy essay brainly

Better safety studies could restore America’s confidence in vaccines

empathy essay brainly

Aspirin after a broken bone: health equity in a $5 bottle

empathy essay brainly

The FDA should withdraw approval of more than 400 tainted medicines

Subscriber picks, stat plus: how unitedhealth turned a questionable artery-screening program into a gold mine, stat plus: the race to build better crispr delivery vehicles is heating up, stat plus: trump keeps losing his train of thought. cognitive experts have theories about why, stat plus: three mdma therapy papers retracted over data integrity concerns, stat plus: a bespoke genetic therapy is helping susannah. can similar drugs be made at scale for other rare diseases.

empathy essay brainly

Advertisement

Supported by

10 Terrific Gena Rowlands Performances to Stream

She delivered vulnerable portraits in movies as varied as “A Woman Under the Influence,” with John Cassavetes, and the drama “The Notebook.”

  • Share full article

In a scene from “A Woman Under the Influence,” Gena Rowlands is seated with her feet on top of a table. There are two crushed metal cans and a box of matches slightly out of focus in the foreground.

By Esther Zuckerman

Gena Rowlands, who died Wednesday at the age of 94, was widely regarded as one of the best actresses of her generation, known for her vulnerable portraits of women in states of crisis. Her most acclaimed performances came through her prolific and intensely creative collaboration with her husband, the director, writer and actor John Cassavetes , who gave her parts like the housewife in turmoil in “A Woman Under the Influence.” Even after his death in 1989, Rowlands would continue to work with family members, starring in the directorial efforts of their son, Nick, and her daughter Zoe. And while she became a star of the 1970s with films that broke new ground in independent cinema, in her later years she was introduced to a younger generation, thanks to Nick Cassavetes’s blockbuster tear-jerker, “The Notebook.” Here is where to watch some of her best work.

Stream on the Criterion Channel or Max

Perhaps the first true example of the magic Rowlands and John Cassavetes could make together came in the form of “Faces.” (Before that, she had an uncredited role in his debut, “Shadows,” as well as a part in his more conventional “A Child Is Waiting,” starring Judy Garland.) But “Faces,” made on a shoestring budget , was the project that started to reveal how unique their partnership could be. In Cassavetes’s drama about tensions between a married couple played by John Marley and Lynn Carlin, Rowlands is Jeannie, a call girl who becomes entangled with the husband in the equation. In Cassavetes’s tight close-ups and long takes you can see how Rowlands embodies the naturalistic milieu he was developing. When we first meet Jeannie she’s a good-time gal, partying with much older men, singing “Jeanie with the Light Brown Hair,” but soon her eyes snap into focus, unwilling to be denigrated, as she develops affection for Marley’s character.

‘A Woman Under the Influence’

We are having trouble retrieving the article content.

Please enable JavaScript in your browser settings.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access. If you are in Reader mode please exit and  log into  your Times account, or  subscribe  for all of The Times.

Thank you for your patience while we verify access.

Already a subscriber?  Log in .

Want all of The Times?  Subscribe .

IMAGES

  1. essay on empathy for class 7

    empathy essay brainly

  2. Empathy Essay

    empathy essay brainly

  3. what does empathy mean?solve these statements

    empathy essay brainly

  4. Empathy Essay

    empathy essay brainly

  5. Essay on empathy for students

    empathy essay brainly

  6. Empathy Essay

    empathy essay brainly

COMMENTS

  1. Understanding others' feelings: what is empathy and why do we need it?

    This is the introductory essay in our series on understanding others' feelings. In it we will examine empathy, including what it is, whether our doctors need more of it, and when too much may ...

  2. Essay on what is the importance of empathy

    Empathy is the experience of understanding another person's thoughts, feelings, and condition from his or her point of view, rather than from one's own. Empathy facilitates prosocial or helping behaviors that come from within, rather than being forced, so that people behave in a more compassionate manner.

  3. Empathy: Definition, Types, and Tips for Practicing

    Empathy allows us to understand and share the feelings of others. Learn why we feel empathy in some situations and not others, different types of empathy, and more.

  4. Empathy

    Empathy is the ability to recognize, understand, and share thoughts and feelings of others, fostering relationships and compassionate behavior.

  5. What does having empathy allow you to do in your research essay?

    The term "empathy" is used to describe a wide range of experiences. Emotion researchers generally define empathy as the ability to sense other people's emotions, coupled with the ability to imagine what someone else might be thinking or feeling.

  6. Empathy

    The concept of empathy is used to refer to a wide range of psychological capacities that are thought of as being central for constituting humans as social creatures allowing us to know what other people are thinking and feeling, to emotionally engage with them, to share their thoughts and feelings, and to care for their well-being.

  7. Empathy 101: 3+ Examples and Psychology Definitions

    Empathy is a complex psychological process that allows us to form bonds with other people. Through empathy, we cry when our friends go through hard times, celebrate their successes, and rage during their times of hardship. Empathy also allows us to feel guilt, shame, and embarrassment, as well as understand jokes and sarcasm.

  8. What Does It Mean to Have Empathy?

    Teaching empathy involves reading others' emotions, considering their perspective and how it's shaped by their experiences, and offering emotional support.

  9. Empathy: What It Is, Why It Matters, and How You Can Improve

    You've been told that empathy is important, but that raises questions. Why does it matter? And how can you grow in it?

  10. Empathy Essay

    Looking for ideas to write an essay on Empathy? We have a great solution 👌 for students who are tired and just want to get high marks for their work.

  11. Which comment on a peer's research essay most clearly shows empathy? A

    Explanation: The question is asking which comment most clearly shows empathy when providing feedback on a peer's research essay. Empathy, in this case, involves understanding and sharing feelings expressed by the author of the essay and offering constructive feedback in a respectful and considerate manner.

  12. Harris to Lay Out Economic Message Focused on High Cost of Living

    The vice president's plans represent more of a reboot of President Biden's economic policies than a radically fresh start.

  13. How can you establish empathy within your argumentative research essay

    Find an answer to your question How can you establish empathy within your argumentative research essay? O A. By criticizing the source of any counterclaims O


  14. 150 word essay on empathy

    Empathy is a highly valued trait and is essential for social interactions. Empathy is the ability to understand a person's emotions and feelings. It is an essential component for both professional as well as personal lives. It is the ability or trait to understand other people's values, beliefs and cultures. Empathy is the power of connection.

  15. Conner O'Malley's Intensely Funny, Deeply Stupid Manosphere

    A cult hero in the comedy world, he specializes in desperately ambitious men doomed to fail. But don't ignore the element of empathy.

  16. Opinion

    Guest Essay. What the Olympics Can Teach Us About Excellence ... Pursuing excellence is, at its core, retaining respect, compassion and empathy for others even in pursuit of being your best, and ...

  17. Can AI help ease medicine's empathy problem?

    Modern medicine has an empathy problem. Artificial intelligence — done right — might be able to help ease it. Despite the proliferation of communication training programs over the past decade ...

  18. What is meant by Empathy ? Explain in the form of an essay.

    The term "empathy" is used to describe a wide range of experiences. Emotion researchers generally define empathy as the ability to sense other people's emotions, coupled with the ability to imagine what someone else might be thinking or feeling.

  19. Describe Emphaty . (Essay type)

    Empathy forms one of the most critical components of creating harmonious relationships. It reduces stress and enhances emotional awareness. People are well attuned to their feelings and emotions. Getting into someone's head can be challenging at times. People tend to be empathetic when they listen to what others have to say.

  20. reflection of empathizing to others?

    Empathy is the ability that lets you understand the feelings, circumstances and emotions of another person. This is different from sympathy which means that you feel compassionate towards another person and somehow feel and experience pity for that person. This is best exemplified when talking to other people.

  21. What is the definition of empathy?

    Empathy is defined as the ability of understanding and being sensitive to the feelings, experiences and/or thoughts of another individual, even when explicit communication about them has not taken place. This ability is related with the capacity to imagine what others are feeling or thinking.

  22. what is empathy ??????????????????

    Answer. Final answer: Empathy is the ability to understand and share the feelings of others. It involves taking on someone else's perspective and experiencing their emotions. Empathy is important for working in groups and understanding diversity. Explanation: Empathy is an affective response in which a person understands, and even feels ...

  23. "It is necessary to develop empathy" essay of 2 pages

    Click here 👆 to get an answer to your question  "It is necessary to develop empathy" essay of 2 pages

  24. 10 Movies Starring Gena Rowlands, From 'The Notebook' to 'Opening Night

    She delivered vulnerable portraits in movies as varied as "A Woman Under the Influence," with John Cassavetes, and the drama "The Notebook."

  25. Write reflective essays about the story, focusing on how ...

    Write reflective essays about the story, focusing on how the theme of empathy was portrayed, the challenges Lily faced, and the overall impact of empathy on the characters and community.

  26. Essay on empathy plays an important role in building social ...

    Find an answer to your question Essay on empathy plays an important role in building social relationships

  27. empathy essay for students

    Empathy Essay: Empathy is the ability to understand an individual emotionally. It is the ability to understand what the other person feels. It is seeing things from their point of view. It is putting yourself in someone else's position. It is the capability of imagining how someone else might be feeling.

  28. What to write in a essay about empathy

    search Ask Question Log in Join for free For parents For teachers Honor code Textbook Solutions Brainly App sakuriinozaki 27.01.2019 English Primary School answer answered You just write about in hindi 'samanbhuti'.